Should the isomorphism theorems be seen as an “interface” between algebra and category theory?Motivation and use for category theory?Meaning of “a mapping preserves structures/properties”What are some examples of hard theorems in category theory?What is the relationship between the second isomorphism theorem and the third one in group theory?On the Importance of the Second and Fourth Isomorphism TheoremsMonomorphisms, epimorphisms and isomorphisms of groups categoryWhat do we need to define a category?Are objects in the category Grp actually groups or isomorphism classes of groups? Is there a difference?What does it mean for two morphisms with different sources and targets to be isomorphic?Describing the monomorphisms and epimorphisms in the category of multisets

Replacing matching entries in one column of a file by another column from a different file

Cross compiling for RPi - error while loading shared libraries

Why is 150k or 200k jobs considered good when there's 300k+ births a month?

Which country benefited the most from UN Security Council vetoes?

meaning of に in 本当に?

Theorems that impeded progress

Did Shadowfax go to Valinor?

Rock identification in KY

Do infinite dimensional systems make sense?

How much of data wrangling is a data scientist's job?

Why "Having chlorophyll without photosynthesis is actually very dangerous" and "like living with a bomb"?

What does it mean to describe someone as a butt steak?

Is it unprofessional to ask if a job posting on GlassDoor is real?

I'm flying to France today and my passport expires in less than 2 months

Intersection point of 2 lines defined by 2 points each

RSA: Danger of using p to create q

Was any UN Security Council vote triple-vetoed?

What are these boxed doors outside store fronts in New York?

Accidentally leaked the solution to an assignment, what to do now? (I'm the prof)

LaTeX: Why are digits allowed in environments, but forbidden in commands?

How does quantile regression compare to logistic regression with the variable split at the quantile?

Watching something be written to a file live with tail

Is it inappropriate for a student to attend their mentor's dissertation defense?

NMaximize is not converging to a solution



Should the isomorphism theorems be seen as an “interface” between algebra and category theory?


Motivation and use for category theory?Meaning of “a mapping preserves structures/properties”What are some examples of hard theorems in category theory?What is the relationship between the second isomorphism theorem and the third one in group theory?On the Importance of the Second and Fourth Isomorphism TheoremsMonomorphisms, epimorphisms and isomorphisms of groups categoryWhat do we need to define a category?Are objects in the category Grp actually groups or isomorphism classes of groups? Is there a difference?What does it mean for two morphisms with different sources and targets to be isomorphic?Describing the monomorphisms and epimorphisms in the category of multisets













4












$begingroup$


My first instinct when I thought about algebra in category theory, was to try to "generalize the isomorphism theorems in category theory".



So I tried to prove the generalization of "the image of a group homomorphism is isomorphic to the quotient group generated by its kernel".



But then I found out that in category subobjects are actually defined in terms of monomorphisms, which for the category Grp is essentially implicitly using that isomorphism theorem.



  • So is it correct that I shouldn't be trying to prove the isomorphism theorems in category theory?


  • Is it correct that instead, the isomorphism theorems are kind of like "interfaces", which justify talking about algebraic structures (among other structuers) in terms of structure preserving morphisms?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$
















    4












    $begingroup$


    My first instinct when I thought about algebra in category theory, was to try to "generalize the isomorphism theorems in category theory".



    So I tried to prove the generalization of "the image of a group homomorphism is isomorphic to the quotient group generated by its kernel".



    But then I found out that in category subobjects are actually defined in terms of monomorphisms, which for the category Grp is essentially implicitly using that isomorphism theorem.



    • So is it correct that I shouldn't be trying to prove the isomorphism theorems in category theory?


    • Is it correct that instead, the isomorphism theorems are kind of like "interfaces", which justify talking about algebraic structures (among other structuers) in terms of structure preserving morphisms?










    share|cite|improve this question









    $endgroup$














      4












      4








      4


      2



      $begingroup$


      My first instinct when I thought about algebra in category theory, was to try to "generalize the isomorphism theorems in category theory".



      So I tried to prove the generalization of "the image of a group homomorphism is isomorphic to the quotient group generated by its kernel".



      But then I found out that in category subobjects are actually defined in terms of monomorphisms, which for the category Grp is essentially implicitly using that isomorphism theorem.



      • So is it correct that I shouldn't be trying to prove the isomorphism theorems in category theory?


      • Is it correct that instead, the isomorphism theorems are kind of like "interfaces", which justify talking about algebraic structures (among other structuers) in terms of structure preserving morphisms?










      share|cite|improve this question









      $endgroup$




      My first instinct when I thought about algebra in category theory, was to try to "generalize the isomorphism theorems in category theory".



      So I tried to prove the generalization of "the image of a group homomorphism is isomorphic to the quotient group generated by its kernel".



      But then I found out that in category subobjects are actually defined in terms of monomorphisms, which for the category Grp is essentially implicitly using that isomorphism theorem.



      • So is it correct that I shouldn't be trying to prove the isomorphism theorems in category theory?


      • Is it correct that instead, the isomorphism theorems are kind of like "interfaces", which justify talking about algebraic structures (among other structuers) in terms of structure preserving morphisms?







      abstract-algebra category-theory group-isomorphism






      share|cite|improve this question













      share|cite|improve this question











      share|cite|improve this question




      share|cite|improve this question










      asked 11 hours ago









      user56834user56834

      3,41821253




      3,41821253




















          2 Answers
          2






          active

          oldest

          votes


















          3












          $begingroup$

          Before addressing your questions I will write here my favorite version of the first isomorphism theorem. As others have commented, you need notions of quotients, images and kernels before even attempting to enunciate such a result. There's more than one way to do this (for example, additive categories). Here we are going to work with concrete categories. Recall the notion of images.




          Definition [kernel]: Let $f colon X to Y$ be a function. The kernel of $f$ is the set $(a,b) in X times X mid f(a)=f(b)$.




          The notion of kernel as defined here is simply the kernel pair of $f$, that is, the pullback of $X xrightarrowf Y xleftarrowf X$.




          Definition [concrete quotients and congruences]: Let $(C,U)$ be a concrete category and $X$ an object of $C$. A concrete quotient of $X$ is an epimorphism $pi colon X to Y$ such that $U(pi)$ is epi and for every object $Z$ of $C$ and every function $f colon U(Y) to U(Z)$, the following are equivalents:



          • There exists a morphism $f' colon Y to Z$ such that $U(f') = f$.

          • There exists a morphism $g colon X to Z$ such that $U(g) = f circ U(pi)$.

          The set $ker(U(pi))$ is called a congruence on $X$.




          If you prefer, you can define concrete quotients as equivalence classes instead. Note that this notion of quotient coincides with topological quotients, for instance, while the usual notion of quotients (that is, epimorphisms) does not. In essence, concrete quotients allow you to complete diagrams in the base category by looking at the underlying diagrams in $Set$. A congruence on an object $X$ is essentially an equivalence relation on $U(X)$ with an associated concrete quotient of $X$. Observe, however, that congruences need not to arise only from $U(pi)$ for $pi$ a concrete quotient.




          Theorem [the First Isomorphism Theorem]: Let $(C,U)$ be a concrete category, where $C$ is complete and $U$ is continuous. Let $q colon X to Z$ be a morphism in $C$ such that $ker(U(q))$ is a congruence on $X$. Then the morphism $m colon X/ker(U(q)) to Z$ (such that $q = m circ pi_q$) is the image of $q$.



          Proof : First of all we must verify that $m$ is a monomorphism. Let $x,y in U(X)$ and $[x],[y]$ their equivalence classes regarding $ker(U(q))$. If $U(m)([x])=U(m)([y])$, then $(U(pi_q) circ U(m))(x)=(U(pi_q) circ U(m))(y)$, hence $U(pi_q circ m)(x)=U(pi_q circ m)(y)$, which implies $U(q)(x)=U(q)(y)$. Therefore $(x,y) in ker(U(q))$ and $[x]=[y]$. $U(m)$ is mono, hence $m$ is as well ($U$ is faithful).



          Now let $m' colon Y to Z$ be a monomorphism and $h colon X to Y$ be a morphism such that $q= m' circ h$. we wish to prove the existence of $f colon X/ker((U(q))) to Y$ such that $m = m' circ f$. If $(x,y) in ker(U(q))$, then $U(q)(x)=U(q)(y)$, hence $U(h)(x)=U(h)(y)$ (since $U$ is continuous and $m'$ is mono, $U(m')$ is mono). By the definition of concrete quotients, there exists a morphism $f colon X/ker((U(q))) to Y$ such that $h = f circ pi_q$. Since $m' circ h = q = m circ pi_q$, we have $m' circ f circ pi_q = m circ pi_q$. Since $pi_q$ is epi, we have $m' circ f = m$.




          Note that, in particular, this isomorphism theorem is valid on the category of topological spaces (with the obvious forgetful functor to $Set$)! What is the problem here? I'll leave that as an exercise.



          Now, addressing the questions:




          So is it correct that I shouldn't be trying to prove the isomorphism theorems in category theory?




          That is not correct. However, you should be aware of the fact that general categories might not always have the structure/properties you need to talk about certain concepts. In that case, however, you should still be able to consider a particular class of categories in which you can prove your desired results.




          Is it correct that instead, the isomorphism theorems are kind of like "interfaces", which justify talking about algebraic structures (among other structuers) in terms of structure preserving morphisms?




          I'm not sure if I understand this question. The fact that homomorphisms between algebraic structures satisfy the isomorphism theorems is certainly a good reason to talk about structure preserving functions (instead of non-structure preserving functions) in certain scenarios. However, in other structures, where the theorem might not be valid (topological spaces for example), it is still "better" to consider structure preserving functions than simply general functions.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$








          • 1




            $begingroup$
            I wish I had known this version of the isomorphism theorem before writing my answer, +1
            $endgroup$
            – Max
            9 hours ago










          • $begingroup$
            For the LaTeX, writing f:Xto Y ($f:Xto Y$) as opposed to fcolon Xto Y ($fcolon Xto Y$) seems easier and renders better... (at least for me).
            $endgroup$
            – Derek Elkins
            1 hour ago


















          2












          $begingroup$

          This isn't a full answer as I don't understand half of the question, and have asked for precision on the other half, but it's too long to be a comment



          No, it's not implicitly using the isomorphism theorem, it's using the fact that (in algebraic structures) the corestriction of an injective morphism to its image is an isomorphism, which is way more basic than the first isomorphism theorem.



          Then, for your questions :



          $bullet$ No you shouldn't try to prove the isomorphism theorem in general categories because it simply isn't true in general. First of all, you would have to have a notion of image and of kernel, which don't usually make sense in an arbitrary category, and even when they do exist, it's not true that the theorem holds. For me to make a precise statement and give counterexamples here you have to tell me what you mean by "image" in a general category, for instance are you referring to this definition ?



          $bullet$ I don't understand this question. Let me just say how I feel about the isomorphism theorem (the first one, the others are just immediate corollaries) for groups, and algebraic structures more generally, in the hope that it will shed some light on them; and perhaps you can edit your post to clarify your question.



          The first isomorphism theorem is basically a tautology : it tells you that if you have a surjective morphism and declare "$x=y$" precisely when $f(x)=f(y)$ then you get an induced map on the new structure when your declaration is true, and that this induced map is injective, and has the same image as the original one. The fact that it has the same image is obvious because there is a factorisation, so I won't mention it. The fact that you get an induced map is also obvious, because if you don't know which antecedent to choose, it doesn't matter, as they all have the same images; so just choose any antecedent.



          Finally, the fact that the induced map is injective is also obvious because you've forced it to be ! If $x,y$ have the same image in the new structure, then any antecedent of them do too, so they have been declared to be equal ! Therefore $x=y$ by the pure will of you, the new structure creator. In other words, the first isomorphism theorem is you wanting a map to be injective, and declaring "it is", and by doing so you simply create a new structure (the quotient structure), on which it is, precisely because you declared it to be.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$













            Your Answer





            StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
            return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
            StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
            StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
            );
            );
            , "mathjax-editing");

            StackExchange.ready(function()
            var channelOptions =
            tags: "".split(" "),
            id: "69"
            ;
            initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

            StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
            // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
            if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
            StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
            createEditor();
            );

            else
            createEditor();

            );

            function createEditor()
            StackExchange.prepareEditor(
            heartbeatType: 'answer',
            autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
            convertImagesToLinks: true,
            noModals: true,
            showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
            reputationToPostImages: 10,
            bindNavPrevention: true,
            postfix: "",
            imageUploader:
            brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
            contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
            allowUrls: true
            ,
            noCode: true, onDemand: true,
            discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
            ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
            );



            );













            draft saved

            draft discarded


















            StackExchange.ready(
            function ()
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3176023%2fshould-the-isomorphism-theorems-be-seen-as-an-interface-between-algebra-and-ca%23new-answer', 'question_page');

            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown

























            2 Answers
            2






            active

            oldest

            votes








            2 Answers
            2






            active

            oldest

            votes









            active

            oldest

            votes






            active

            oldest

            votes









            3












            $begingroup$

            Before addressing your questions I will write here my favorite version of the first isomorphism theorem. As others have commented, you need notions of quotients, images and kernels before even attempting to enunciate such a result. There's more than one way to do this (for example, additive categories). Here we are going to work with concrete categories. Recall the notion of images.




            Definition [kernel]: Let $f colon X to Y$ be a function. The kernel of $f$ is the set $(a,b) in X times X mid f(a)=f(b)$.




            The notion of kernel as defined here is simply the kernel pair of $f$, that is, the pullback of $X xrightarrowf Y xleftarrowf X$.




            Definition [concrete quotients and congruences]: Let $(C,U)$ be a concrete category and $X$ an object of $C$. A concrete quotient of $X$ is an epimorphism $pi colon X to Y$ such that $U(pi)$ is epi and for every object $Z$ of $C$ and every function $f colon U(Y) to U(Z)$, the following are equivalents:



            • There exists a morphism $f' colon Y to Z$ such that $U(f') = f$.

            • There exists a morphism $g colon X to Z$ such that $U(g) = f circ U(pi)$.

            The set $ker(U(pi))$ is called a congruence on $X$.




            If you prefer, you can define concrete quotients as equivalence classes instead. Note that this notion of quotient coincides with topological quotients, for instance, while the usual notion of quotients (that is, epimorphisms) does not. In essence, concrete quotients allow you to complete diagrams in the base category by looking at the underlying diagrams in $Set$. A congruence on an object $X$ is essentially an equivalence relation on $U(X)$ with an associated concrete quotient of $X$. Observe, however, that congruences need not to arise only from $U(pi)$ for $pi$ a concrete quotient.




            Theorem [the First Isomorphism Theorem]: Let $(C,U)$ be a concrete category, where $C$ is complete and $U$ is continuous. Let $q colon X to Z$ be a morphism in $C$ such that $ker(U(q))$ is a congruence on $X$. Then the morphism $m colon X/ker(U(q)) to Z$ (such that $q = m circ pi_q$) is the image of $q$.



            Proof : First of all we must verify that $m$ is a monomorphism. Let $x,y in U(X)$ and $[x],[y]$ their equivalence classes regarding $ker(U(q))$. If $U(m)([x])=U(m)([y])$, then $(U(pi_q) circ U(m))(x)=(U(pi_q) circ U(m))(y)$, hence $U(pi_q circ m)(x)=U(pi_q circ m)(y)$, which implies $U(q)(x)=U(q)(y)$. Therefore $(x,y) in ker(U(q))$ and $[x]=[y]$. $U(m)$ is mono, hence $m$ is as well ($U$ is faithful).



            Now let $m' colon Y to Z$ be a monomorphism and $h colon X to Y$ be a morphism such that $q= m' circ h$. we wish to prove the existence of $f colon X/ker((U(q))) to Y$ such that $m = m' circ f$. If $(x,y) in ker(U(q))$, then $U(q)(x)=U(q)(y)$, hence $U(h)(x)=U(h)(y)$ (since $U$ is continuous and $m'$ is mono, $U(m')$ is mono). By the definition of concrete quotients, there exists a morphism $f colon X/ker((U(q))) to Y$ such that $h = f circ pi_q$. Since $m' circ h = q = m circ pi_q$, we have $m' circ f circ pi_q = m circ pi_q$. Since $pi_q$ is epi, we have $m' circ f = m$.




            Note that, in particular, this isomorphism theorem is valid on the category of topological spaces (with the obvious forgetful functor to $Set$)! What is the problem here? I'll leave that as an exercise.



            Now, addressing the questions:




            So is it correct that I shouldn't be trying to prove the isomorphism theorems in category theory?




            That is not correct. However, you should be aware of the fact that general categories might not always have the structure/properties you need to talk about certain concepts. In that case, however, you should still be able to consider a particular class of categories in which you can prove your desired results.




            Is it correct that instead, the isomorphism theorems are kind of like "interfaces", which justify talking about algebraic structures (among other structuers) in terms of structure preserving morphisms?




            I'm not sure if I understand this question. The fact that homomorphisms between algebraic structures satisfy the isomorphism theorems is certainly a good reason to talk about structure preserving functions (instead of non-structure preserving functions) in certain scenarios. However, in other structures, where the theorem might not be valid (topological spaces for example), it is still "better" to consider structure preserving functions than simply general functions.






            share|cite|improve this answer











            $endgroup$








            • 1




              $begingroup$
              I wish I had known this version of the isomorphism theorem before writing my answer, +1
              $endgroup$
              – Max
              9 hours ago










            • $begingroup$
              For the LaTeX, writing f:Xto Y ($f:Xto Y$) as opposed to fcolon Xto Y ($fcolon Xto Y$) seems easier and renders better... (at least for me).
              $endgroup$
              – Derek Elkins
              1 hour ago















            3












            $begingroup$

            Before addressing your questions I will write here my favorite version of the first isomorphism theorem. As others have commented, you need notions of quotients, images and kernels before even attempting to enunciate such a result. There's more than one way to do this (for example, additive categories). Here we are going to work with concrete categories. Recall the notion of images.




            Definition [kernel]: Let $f colon X to Y$ be a function. The kernel of $f$ is the set $(a,b) in X times X mid f(a)=f(b)$.




            The notion of kernel as defined here is simply the kernel pair of $f$, that is, the pullback of $X xrightarrowf Y xleftarrowf X$.




            Definition [concrete quotients and congruences]: Let $(C,U)$ be a concrete category and $X$ an object of $C$. A concrete quotient of $X$ is an epimorphism $pi colon X to Y$ such that $U(pi)$ is epi and for every object $Z$ of $C$ and every function $f colon U(Y) to U(Z)$, the following are equivalents:



            • There exists a morphism $f' colon Y to Z$ such that $U(f') = f$.

            • There exists a morphism $g colon X to Z$ such that $U(g) = f circ U(pi)$.

            The set $ker(U(pi))$ is called a congruence on $X$.




            If you prefer, you can define concrete quotients as equivalence classes instead. Note that this notion of quotient coincides with topological quotients, for instance, while the usual notion of quotients (that is, epimorphisms) does not. In essence, concrete quotients allow you to complete diagrams in the base category by looking at the underlying diagrams in $Set$. A congruence on an object $X$ is essentially an equivalence relation on $U(X)$ with an associated concrete quotient of $X$. Observe, however, that congruences need not to arise only from $U(pi)$ for $pi$ a concrete quotient.




            Theorem [the First Isomorphism Theorem]: Let $(C,U)$ be a concrete category, where $C$ is complete and $U$ is continuous. Let $q colon X to Z$ be a morphism in $C$ such that $ker(U(q))$ is a congruence on $X$. Then the morphism $m colon X/ker(U(q)) to Z$ (such that $q = m circ pi_q$) is the image of $q$.



            Proof : First of all we must verify that $m$ is a monomorphism. Let $x,y in U(X)$ and $[x],[y]$ their equivalence classes regarding $ker(U(q))$. If $U(m)([x])=U(m)([y])$, then $(U(pi_q) circ U(m))(x)=(U(pi_q) circ U(m))(y)$, hence $U(pi_q circ m)(x)=U(pi_q circ m)(y)$, which implies $U(q)(x)=U(q)(y)$. Therefore $(x,y) in ker(U(q))$ and $[x]=[y]$. $U(m)$ is mono, hence $m$ is as well ($U$ is faithful).



            Now let $m' colon Y to Z$ be a monomorphism and $h colon X to Y$ be a morphism such that $q= m' circ h$. we wish to prove the existence of $f colon X/ker((U(q))) to Y$ such that $m = m' circ f$. If $(x,y) in ker(U(q))$, then $U(q)(x)=U(q)(y)$, hence $U(h)(x)=U(h)(y)$ (since $U$ is continuous and $m'$ is mono, $U(m')$ is mono). By the definition of concrete quotients, there exists a morphism $f colon X/ker((U(q))) to Y$ such that $h = f circ pi_q$. Since $m' circ h = q = m circ pi_q$, we have $m' circ f circ pi_q = m circ pi_q$. Since $pi_q$ is epi, we have $m' circ f = m$.




            Note that, in particular, this isomorphism theorem is valid on the category of topological spaces (with the obvious forgetful functor to $Set$)! What is the problem here? I'll leave that as an exercise.



            Now, addressing the questions:




            So is it correct that I shouldn't be trying to prove the isomorphism theorems in category theory?




            That is not correct. However, you should be aware of the fact that general categories might not always have the structure/properties you need to talk about certain concepts. In that case, however, you should still be able to consider a particular class of categories in which you can prove your desired results.




            Is it correct that instead, the isomorphism theorems are kind of like "interfaces", which justify talking about algebraic structures (among other structuers) in terms of structure preserving morphisms?




            I'm not sure if I understand this question. The fact that homomorphisms between algebraic structures satisfy the isomorphism theorems is certainly a good reason to talk about structure preserving functions (instead of non-structure preserving functions) in certain scenarios. However, in other structures, where the theorem might not be valid (topological spaces for example), it is still "better" to consider structure preserving functions than simply general functions.






            share|cite|improve this answer











            $endgroup$








            • 1




              $begingroup$
              I wish I had known this version of the isomorphism theorem before writing my answer, +1
              $endgroup$
              – Max
              9 hours ago










            • $begingroup$
              For the LaTeX, writing f:Xto Y ($f:Xto Y$) as opposed to fcolon Xto Y ($fcolon Xto Y$) seems easier and renders better... (at least for me).
              $endgroup$
              – Derek Elkins
              1 hour ago













            3












            3








            3





            $begingroup$

            Before addressing your questions I will write here my favorite version of the first isomorphism theorem. As others have commented, you need notions of quotients, images and kernels before even attempting to enunciate such a result. There's more than one way to do this (for example, additive categories). Here we are going to work with concrete categories. Recall the notion of images.




            Definition [kernel]: Let $f colon X to Y$ be a function. The kernel of $f$ is the set $(a,b) in X times X mid f(a)=f(b)$.




            The notion of kernel as defined here is simply the kernel pair of $f$, that is, the pullback of $X xrightarrowf Y xleftarrowf X$.




            Definition [concrete quotients and congruences]: Let $(C,U)$ be a concrete category and $X$ an object of $C$. A concrete quotient of $X$ is an epimorphism $pi colon X to Y$ such that $U(pi)$ is epi and for every object $Z$ of $C$ and every function $f colon U(Y) to U(Z)$, the following are equivalents:



            • There exists a morphism $f' colon Y to Z$ such that $U(f') = f$.

            • There exists a morphism $g colon X to Z$ such that $U(g) = f circ U(pi)$.

            The set $ker(U(pi))$ is called a congruence on $X$.




            If you prefer, you can define concrete quotients as equivalence classes instead. Note that this notion of quotient coincides with topological quotients, for instance, while the usual notion of quotients (that is, epimorphisms) does not. In essence, concrete quotients allow you to complete diagrams in the base category by looking at the underlying diagrams in $Set$. A congruence on an object $X$ is essentially an equivalence relation on $U(X)$ with an associated concrete quotient of $X$. Observe, however, that congruences need not to arise only from $U(pi)$ for $pi$ a concrete quotient.




            Theorem [the First Isomorphism Theorem]: Let $(C,U)$ be a concrete category, where $C$ is complete and $U$ is continuous. Let $q colon X to Z$ be a morphism in $C$ such that $ker(U(q))$ is a congruence on $X$. Then the morphism $m colon X/ker(U(q)) to Z$ (such that $q = m circ pi_q$) is the image of $q$.



            Proof : First of all we must verify that $m$ is a monomorphism. Let $x,y in U(X)$ and $[x],[y]$ their equivalence classes regarding $ker(U(q))$. If $U(m)([x])=U(m)([y])$, then $(U(pi_q) circ U(m))(x)=(U(pi_q) circ U(m))(y)$, hence $U(pi_q circ m)(x)=U(pi_q circ m)(y)$, which implies $U(q)(x)=U(q)(y)$. Therefore $(x,y) in ker(U(q))$ and $[x]=[y]$. $U(m)$ is mono, hence $m$ is as well ($U$ is faithful).



            Now let $m' colon Y to Z$ be a monomorphism and $h colon X to Y$ be a morphism such that $q= m' circ h$. we wish to prove the existence of $f colon X/ker((U(q))) to Y$ such that $m = m' circ f$. If $(x,y) in ker(U(q))$, then $U(q)(x)=U(q)(y)$, hence $U(h)(x)=U(h)(y)$ (since $U$ is continuous and $m'$ is mono, $U(m')$ is mono). By the definition of concrete quotients, there exists a morphism $f colon X/ker((U(q))) to Y$ such that $h = f circ pi_q$. Since $m' circ h = q = m circ pi_q$, we have $m' circ f circ pi_q = m circ pi_q$. Since $pi_q$ is epi, we have $m' circ f = m$.




            Note that, in particular, this isomorphism theorem is valid on the category of topological spaces (with the obvious forgetful functor to $Set$)! What is the problem here? I'll leave that as an exercise.



            Now, addressing the questions:




            So is it correct that I shouldn't be trying to prove the isomorphism theorems in category theory?




            That is not correct. However, you should be aware of the fact that general categories might not always have the structure/properties you need to talk about certain concepts. In that case, however, you should still be able to consider a particular class of categories in which you can prove your desired results.




            Is it correct that instead, the isomorphism theorems are kind of like "interfaces", which justify talking about algebraic structures (among other structuers) in terms of structure preserving morphisms?




            I'm not sure if I understand this question. The fact that homomorphisms between algebraic structures satisfy the isomorphism theorems is certainly a good reason to talk about structure preserving functions (instead of non-structure preserving functions) in certain scenarios. However, in other structures, where the theorem might not be valid (topological spaces for example), it is still "better" to consider structure preserving functions than simply general functions.






            share|cite|improve this answer











            $endgroup$



            Before addressing your questions I will write here my favorite version of the first isomorphism theorem. As others have commented, you need notions of quotients, images and kernels before even attempting to enunciate such a result. There's more than one way to do this (for example, additive categories). Here we are going to work with concrete categories. Recall the notion of images.




            Definition [kernel]: Let $f colon X to Y$ be a function. The kernel of $f$ is the set $(a,b) in X times X mid f(a)=f(b)$.




            The notion of kernel as defined here is simply the kernel pair of $f$, that is, the pullback of $X xrightarrowf Y xleftarrowf X$.




            Definition [concrete quotients and congruences]: Let $(C,U)$ be a concrete category and $X$ an object of $C$. A concrete quotient of $X$ is an epimorphism $pi colon X to Y$ such that $U(pi)$ is epi and for every object $Z$ of $C$ and every function $f colon U(Y) to U(Z)$, the following are equivalents:



            • There exists a morphism $f' colon Y to Z$ such that $U(f') = f$.

            • There exists a morphism $g colon X to Z$ such that $U(g) = f circ U(pi)$.

            The set $ker(U(pi))$ is called a congruence on $X$.




            If you prefer, you can define concrete quotients as equivalence classes instead. Note that this notion of quotient coincides with topological quotients, for instance, while the usual notion of quotients (that is, epimorphisms) does not. In essence, concrete quotients allow you to complete diagrams in the base category by looking at the underlying diagrams in $Set$. A congruence on an object $X$ is essentially an equivalence relation on $U(X)$ with an associated concrete quotient of $X$. Observe, however, that congruences need not to arise only from $U(pi)$ for $pi$ a concrete quotient.




            Theorem [the First Isomorphism Theorem]: Let $(C,U)$ be a concrete category, where $C$ is complete and $U$ is continuous. Let $q colon X to Z$ be a morphism in $C$ such that $ker(U(q))$ is a congruence on $X$. Then the morphism $m colon X/ker(U(q)) to Z$ (such that $q = m circ pi_q$) is the image of $q$.



            Proof : First of all we must verify that $m$ is a monomorphism. Let $x,y in U(X)$ and $[x],[y]$ their equivalence classes regarding $ker(U(q))$. If $U(m)([x])=U(m)([y])$, then $(U(pi_q) circ U(m))(x)=(U(pi_q) circ U(m))(y)$, hence $U(pi_q circ m)(x)=U(pi_q circ m)(y)$, which implies $U(q)(x)=U(q)(y)$. Therefore $(x,y) in ker(U(q))$ and $[x]=[y]$. $U(m)$ is mono, hence $m$ is as well ($U$ is faithful).



            Now let $m' colon Y to Z$ be a monomorphism and $h colon X to Y$ be a morphism such that $q= m' circ h$. we wish to prove the existence of $f colon X/ker((U(q))) to Y$ such that $m = m' circ f$. If $(x,y) in ker(U(q))$, then $U(q)(x)=U(q)(y)$, hence $U(h)(x)=U(h)(y)$ (since $U$ is continuous and $m'$ is mono, $U(m')$ is mono). By the definition of concrete quotients, there exists a morphism $f colon X/ker((U(q))) to Y$ such that $h = f circ pi_q$. Since $m' circ h = q = m circ pi_q$, we have $m' circ f circ pi_q = m circ pi_q$. Since $pi_q$ is epi, we have $m' circ f = m$.




            Note that, in particular, this isomorphism theorem is valid on the category of topological spaces (with the obvious forgetful functor to $Set$)! What is the problem here? I'll leave that as an exercise.



            Now, addressing the questions:




            So is it correct that I shouldn't be trying to prove the isomorphism theorems in category theory?




            That is not correct. However, you should be aware of the fact that general categories might not always have the structure/properties you need to talk about certain concepts. In that case, however, you should still be able to consider a particular class of categories in which you can prove your desired results.




            Is it correct that instead, the isomorphism theorems are kind of like "interfaces", which justify talking about algebraic structures (among other structuers) in terms of structure preserving morphisms?




            I'm not sure if I understand this question. The fact that homomorphisms between algebraic structures satisfy the isomorphism theorems is certainly a good reason to talk about structure preserving functions (instead of non-structure preserving functions) in certain scenarios. However, in other structures, where the theorem might not be valid (topological spaces for example), it is still "better" to consider structure preserving functions than simply general functions.







            share|cite|improve this answer














            share|cite|improve this answer



            share|cite|improve this answer








            edited 8 hours ago

























            answered 10 hours ago









            Hilario FernandesHilario Fernandes

            430410




            430410







            • 1




              $begingroup$
              I wish I had known this version of the isomorphism theorem before writing my answer, +1
              $endgroup$
              – Max
              9 hours ago










            • $begingroup$
              For the LaTeX, writing f:Xto Y ($f:Xto Y$) as opposed to fcolon Xto Y ($fcolon Xto Y$) seems easier and renders better... (at least for me).
              $endgroup$
              – Derek Elkins
              1 hour ago












            • 1




              $begingroup$
              I wish I had known this version of the isomorphism theorem before writing my answer, +1
              $endgroup$
              – Max
              9 hours ago










            • $begingroup$
              For the LaTeX, writing f:Xto Y ($f:Xto Y$) as opposed to fcolon Xto Y ($fcolon Xto Y$) seems easier and renders better... (at least for me).
              $endgroup$
              – Derek Elkins
              1 hour ago







            1




            1




            $begingroup$
            I wish I had known this version of the isomorphism theorem before writing my answer, +1
            $endgroup$
            – Max
            9 hours ago




            $begingroup$
            I wish I had known this version of the isomorphism theorem before writing my answer, +1
            $endgroup$
            – Max
            9 hours ago












            $begingroup$
            For the LaTeX, writing f:Xto Y ($f:Xto Y$) as opposed to fcolon Xto Y ($fcolon Xto Y$) seems easier and renders better... (at least for me).
            $endgroup$
            – Derek Elkins
            1 hour ago




            $begingroup$
            For the LaTeX, writing f:Xto Y ($f:Xto Y$) as opposed to fcolon Xto Y ($fcolon Xto Y$) seems easier and renders better... (at least for me).
            $endgroup$
            – Derek Elkins
            1 hour ago











            2












            $begingroup$

            This isn't a full answer as I don't understand half of the question, and have asked for precision on the other half, but it's too long to be a comment



            No, it's not implicitly using the isomorphism theorem, it's using the fact that (in algebraic structures) the corestriction of an injective morphism to its image is an isomorphism, which is way more basic than the first isomorphism theorem.



            Then, for your questions :



            $bullet$ No you shouldn't try to prove the isomorphism theorem in general categories because it simply isn't true in general. First of all, you would have to have a notion of image and of kernel, which don't usually make sense in an arbitrary category, and even when they do exist, it's not true that the theorem holds. For me to make a precise statement and give counterexamples here you have to tell me what you mean by "image" in a general category, for instance are you referring to this definition ?



            $bullet$ I don't understand this question. Let me just say how I feel about the isomorphism theorem (the first one, the others are just immediate corollaries) for groups, and algebraic structures more generally, in the hope that it will shed some light on them; and perhaps you can edit your post to clarify your question.



            The first isomorphism theorem is basically a tautology : it tells you that if you have a surjective morphism and declare "$x=y$" precisely when $f(x)=f(y)$ then you get an induced map on the new structure when your declaration is true, and that this induced map is injective, and has the same image as the original one. The fact that it has the same image is obvious because there is a factorisation, so I won't mention it. The fact that you get an induced map is also obvious, because if you don't know which antecedent to choose, it doesn't matter, as they all have the same images; so just choose any antecedent.



            Finally, the fact that the induced map is injective is also obvious because you've forced it to be ! If $x,y$ have the same image in the new structure, then any antecedent of them do too, so they have been declared to be equal ! Therefore $x=y$ by the pure will of you, the new structure creator. In other words, the first isomorphism theorem is you wanting a map to be injective, and declaring "it is", and by doing so you simply create a new structure (the quotient structure), on which it is, precisely because you declared it to be.






            share|cite|improve this answer









            $endgroup$

















              2












              $begingroup$

              This isn't a full answer as I don't understand half of the question, and have asked for precision on the other half, but it's too long to be a comment



              No, it's not implicitly using the isomorphism theorem, it's using the fact that (in algebraic structures) the corestriction of an injective morphism to its image is an isomorphism, which is way more basic than the first isomorphism theorem.



              Then, for your questions :



              $bullet$ No you shouldn't try to prove the isomorphism theorem in general categories because it simply isn't true in general. First of all, you would have to have a notion of image and of kernel, which don't usually make sense in an arbitrary category, and even when they do exist, it's not true that the theorem holds. For me to make a precise statement and give counterexamples here you have to tell me what you mean by "image" in a general category, for instance are you referring to this definition ?



              $bullet$ I don't understand this question. Let me just say how I feel about the isomorphism theorem (the first one, the others are just immediate corollaries) for groups, and algebraic structures more generally, in the hope that it will shed some light on them; and perhaps you can edit your post to clarify your question.



              The first isomorphism theorem is basically a tautology : it tells you that if you have a surjective morphism and declare "$x=y$" precisely when $f(x)=f(y)$ then you get an induced map on the new structure when your declaration is true, and that this induced map is injective, and has the same image as the original one. The fact that it has the same image is obvious because there is a factorisation, so I won't mention it. The fact that you get an induced map is also obvious, because if you don't know which antecedent to choose, it doesn't matter, as they all have the same images; so just choose any antecedent.



              Finally, the fact that the induced map is injective is also obvious because you've forced it to be ! If $x,y$ have the same image in the new structure, then any antecedent of them do too, so they have been declared to be equal ! Therefore $x=y$ by the pure will of you, the new structure creator. In other words, the first isomorphism theorem is you wanting a map to be injective, and declaring "it is", and by doing so you simply create a new structure (the quotient structure), on which it is, precisely because you declared it to be.






              share|cite|improve this answer









              $endgroup$















                2












                2








                2





                $begingroup$

                This isn't a full answer as I don't understand half of the question, and have asked for precision on the other half, but it's too long to be a comment



                No, it's not implicitly using the isomorphism theorem, it's using the fact that (in algebraic structures) the corestriction of an injective morphism to its image is an isomorphism, which is way more basic than the first isomorphism theorem.



                Then, for your questions :



                $bullet$ No you shouldn't try to prove the isomorphism theorem in general categories because it simply isn't true in general. First of all, you would have to have a notion of image and of kernel, which don't usually make sense in an arbitrary category, and even when they do exist, it's not true that the theorem holds. For me to make a precise statement and give counterexamples here you have to tell me what you mean by "image" in a general category, for instance are you referring to this definition ?



                $bullet$ I don't understand this question. Let me just say how I feel about the isomorphism theorem (the first one, the others are just immediate corollaries) for groups, and algebraic structures more generally, in the hope that it will shed some light on them; and perhaps you can edit your post to clarify your question.



                The first isomorphism theorem is basically a tautology : it tells you that if you have a surjective morphism and declare "$x=y$" precisely when $f(x)=f(y)$ then you get an induced map on the new structure when your declaration is true, and that this induced map is injective, and has the same image as the original one. The fact that it has the same image is obvious because there is a factorisation, so I won't mention it. The fact that you get an induced map is also obvious, because if you don't know which antecedent to choose, it doesn't matter, as they all have the same images; so just choose any antecedent.



                Finally, the fact that the induced map is injective is also obvious because you've forced it to be ! If $x,y$ have the same image in the new structure, then any antecedent of them do too, so they have been declared to be equal ! Therefore $x=y$ by the pure will of you, the new structure creator. In other words, the first isomorphism theorem is you wanting a map to be injective, and declaring "it is", and by doing so you simply create a new structure (the quotient structure), on which it is, precisely because you declared it to be.






                share|cite|improve this answer









                $endgroup$



                This isn't a full answer as I don't understand half of the question, and have asked for precision on the other half, but it's too long to be a comment



                No, it's not implicitly using the isomorphism theorem, it's using the fact that (in algebraic structures) the corestriction of an injective morphism to its image is an isomorphism, which is way more basic than the first isomorphism theorem.



                Then, for your questions :



                $bullet$ No you shouldn't try to prove the isomorphism theorem in general categories because it simply isn't true in general. First of all, you would have to have a notion of image and of kernel, which don't usually make sense in an arbitrary category, and even when they do exist, it's not true that the theorem holds. For me to make a precise statement and give counterexamples here you have to tell me what you mean by "image" in a general category, for instance are you referring to this definition ?



                $bullet$ I don't understand this question. Let me just say how I feel about the isomorphism theorem (the first one, the others are just immediate corollaries) for groups, and algebraic structures more generally, in the hope that it will shed some light on them; and perhaps you can edit your post to clarify your question.



                The first isomorphism theorem is basically a tautology : it tells you that if you have a surjective morphism and declare "$x=y$" precisely when $f(x)=f(y)$ then you get an induced map on the new structure when your declaration is true, and that this induced map is injective, and has the same image as the original one. The fact that it has the same image is obvious because there is a factorisation, so I won't mention it. The fact that you get an induced map is also obvious, because if you don't know which antecedent to choose, it doesn't matter, as they all have the same images; so just choose any antecedent.



                Finally, the fact that the induced map is injective is also obvious because you've forced it to be ! If $x,y$ have the same image in the new structure, then any antecedent of them do too, so they have been declared to be equal ! Therefore $x=y$ by the pure will of you, the new structure creator. In other words, the first isomorphism theorem is you wanting a map to be injective, and declaring "it is", and by doing so you simply create a new structure (the quotient structure), on which it is, precisely because you declared it to be.







                share|cite|improve this answer












                share|cite|improve this answer



                share|cite|improve this answer










                answered 11 hours ago









                MaxMax

                16k11144




                16k11144



























                    draft saved

                    draft discarded
















































                    Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


                    • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                    But avoid


                    • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                    • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.

                    Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


                    To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                    draft saved


                    draft discarded














                    StackExchange.ready(
                    function ()
                    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3176023%2fshould-the-isomorphism-theorems-be-seen-as-an-interface-between-algebra-and-ca%23new-answer', 'question_page');

                    );

                    Post as a guest















                    Required, but never shown





















































                    Required, but never shown














                    Required, but never shown












                    Required, but never shown







                    Required, but never shown

































                    Required, but never shown














                    Required, but never shown












                    Required, but never shown







                    Required, but never shown







                    Popular posts from this blog

                    Canceling a color specificationRandomly assigning color to Graphics3D objects?Default color for Filling in Mathematica 9Coloring specific elements of sets with a prime modified order in an array plotHow to pick a color differing significantly from the colors already in a given color list?Detection of the text colorColor numbers based on their valueCan color schemes for use with ColorData include opacity specification?My dynamic color schemes

                    Invision Community Contents History See also References External links Navigation menuProprietaryinvisioncommunity.comIPS Community ForumsIPS Community Forumsthis blog entry"License Changes, IP.Board 3.4, and the Future""Interview -- Matt Mecham of Ibforums""CEO Invision Power Board, Matt Mecham Is a Liar, Thief!"IPB License Explanation 1.3, 1.3.1, 2.0, and 2.1ArchivedSecurity Fixes, Updates And Enhancements For IPB 1.3.1Archived"New Demo Accounts - Invision Power Services"the original"New Default Skin"the original"Invision Power Board 3.0.0 and Applications Released"the original"Archived copy"the original"Perpetual licenses being done away with""Release Notes - Invision Power Services""Introducing: IPS Community Suite 4!"Invision Community Release Notes

                    199年 目錄 大件事 到箇年出世嗰人 到箇年死嗰人 節慶、風俗習慣 導覽選單