Congruence of angles axiomIn neutral geometry, can a family of parallel lines leave holes in the plane?Stuck on geometry provingWithout using angle measure how do I prove two lines are parallel to the same line are parallel to each other?AAS Congruence Included Side?Prove congruence of pentagons with all right angles.Inscribing rhombus in a triangle's angle in only eight compass-and-straightedge stepsLet $x_1$ be the length $DE$ and $x_2$ is the length $BC$. Prove $x_1<x_2$.Visual proof of isosceles base-angle congruency?Neutral geometry: If one triangle has angle-sum $180^circ$, then all triangles have angle-sum $180^circ$
Connect Mac CD drive to another Mac
When was “sf” first used to describe science fiction?
Difference between head and tail
How much income am I getting by renting my house?
Why are KDFs slow? Is using a KDF more secure than using the original secret?
Shortest way to get an EOF Error
How did Ron get five hundred Chocolate Frog cards?
'The Kukhtarev's model' or 'Kukhtarev's model' ('John's car' or 'The John's car')?
Are there any rules around when something can be described as "based on a true story"?
What are the consequences for downstream actors of redistributing a work under a wider CC license than the copyright holder authorized?
R or Cpp for some finance work involved complex numbers?
algebra permutations
Do you say "good game" after a game in which your opponent played poorly?
33 Months on Death Row
Why does 1.1.1.1 not resolve archive.is?
How can I cut a metal pipe while preserving the wires inside?
What causes standard door hinges to close up to a certain amount automatically?
What is the German word for: "It only works when I try to show you how it does not work"?
SSD or HDD for server
Is it reasonable to ask candidates to create a profile on Google Scholar?
Why are seats at the rear of a plane sometimes unavailable even though many other seats are available in the plane?
Is it possible to cross Arctic Ocean on ski/kayak undetectable now?
How to protect my Wi-Fi password from being displayed by Android phones when sharing it with QR code?
Novel set in the future, children cannot change the class they are born into, one class is made uneducated by associating books with pain
Congruence of angles axiom
In neutral geometry, can a family of parallel lines leave holes in the plane?Stuck on geometry provingWithout using angle measure how do I prove two lines are parallel to the same line are parallel to each other?AAS Congruence Included Side?Prove congruence of pentagons with all right angles.Inscribing rhombus in a triangle's angle in only eight compass-and-straightedge stepsLet $x_1$ be the length $DE$ and $x_2$ is the length $BC$. Prove $x_1<x_2$.Visual proof of isosceles base-angle congruency?Neutral geometry: If one triangle has angle-sum $180^circ$, then all triangles have angle-sum $180^circ$
.everyoneloves__top-leaderboard:empty,.everyoneloves__mid-leaderboard:empty,.everyoneloves__bot-mid-leaderboard:empty
margin-bottom:0;
.everyonelovesstackoverflowposition:absolute;height:1px;width:1px;opacity:0;top:0;left:0;pointer-events:none;
$begingroup$
In my geometry book, the following statement is provided as axiom of congruence.
Let $ABC$ and $A'B'C'$ be two triangles. If $AB equiv A'B'$, $AC equiv A'C'$ and $ angle BAC equiv B'A'C'$ then $ angle ABC equiv A'B'C'$
I honestly have no idea where this comes from. Note that we use this axiom to prove $SSS$, $ASA$ and $SAS$.
Could someone provide intuition for something like this? It has to be obvious if it's used as an axiom.. right? I'm having trouble memorising something like that and using it to prove things. Not to mention the order here is extremely important.
EDIT:
As an extra note in the book it says, if we change it to $AC equiv A'C'$ , $ AB equiv A'B'$ and $angle CAB = angle C'A'B'$ then $angle ACB equiv angle A'C'B'$
geometry axioms congruences-geometry
$endgroup$
add a comment
|
$begingroup$
In my geometry book, the following statement is provided as axiom of congruence.
Let $ABC$ and $A'B'C'$ be two triangles. If $AB equiv A'B'$, $AC equiv A'C'$ and $ angle BAC equiv B'A'C'$ then $ angle ABC equiv A'B'C'$
I honestly have no idea where this comes from. Note that we use this axiom to prove $SSS$, $ASA$ and $SAS$.
Could someone provide intuition for something like this? It has to be obvious if it's used as an axiom.. right? I'm having trouble memorising something like that and using it to prove things. Not to mention the order here is extremely important.
EDIT:
As an extra note in the book it says, if we change it to $AC equiv A'C'$ , $ AB equiv A'B'$ and $angle CAB = angle C'A'B'$ then $angle ACB equiv angle A'C'B'$
geometry axioms congruences-geometry
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Try to construct two non-congruent triangles with the given quantities—you won’t succeed.
$endgroup$
– Michael Hoppe
8 hours ago
add a comment
|
$begingroup$
In my geometry book, the following statement is provided as axiom of congruence.
Let $ABC$ and $A'B'C'$ be two triangles. If $AB equiv A'B'$, $AC equiv A'C'$ and $ angle BAC equiv B'A'C'$ then $ angle ABC equiv A'B'C'$
I honestly have no idea where this comes from. Note that we use this axiom to prove $SSS$, $ASA$ and $SAS$.
Could someone provide intuition for something like this? It has to be obvious if it's used as an axiom.. right? I'm having trouble memorising something like that and using it to prove things. Not to mention the order here is extremely important.
EDIT:
As an extra note in the book it says, if we change it to $AC equiv A'C'$ , $ AB equiv A'B'$ and $angle CAB = angle C'A'B'$ then $angle ACB equiv angle A'C'B'$
geometry axioms congruences-geometry
$endgroup$
In my geometry book, the following statement is provided as axiom of congruence.
Let $ABC$ and $A'B'C'$ be two triangles. If $AB equiv A'B'$, $AC equiv A'C'$ and $ angle BAC equiv B'A'C'$ then $ angle ABC equiv A'B'C'$
I honestly have no idea where this comes from. Note that we use this axiom to prove $SSS$, $ASA$ and $SAS$.
Could someone provide intuition for something like this? It has to be obvious if it's used as an axiom.. right? I'm having trouble memorising something like that and using it to prove things. Not to mention the order here is extremely important.
EDIT:
As an extra note in the book it says, if we change it to $AC equiv A'C'$ , $ AB equiv A'B'$ and $angle CAB = angle C'A'B'$ then $angle ACB equiv angle A'C'B'$
geometry axioms congruences-geometry
geometry axioms congruences-geometry
edited 7 hours ago
DreaDk
asked 8 hours ago
DreaDkDreaDk
7081 gold badge3 silver badges18 bronze badges
7081 gold badge3 silver badges18 bronze badges
$begingroup$
Try to construct two non-congruent triangles with the given quantities—you won’t succeed.
$endgroup$
– Michael Hoppe
8 hours ago
add a comment
|
$begingroup$
Try to construct two non-congruent triangles with the given quantities—you won’t succeed.
$endgroup$
– Michael Hoppe
8 hours ago
$begingroup$
Try to construct two non-congruent triangles with the given quantities—you won’t succeed.
$endgroup$
– Michael Hoppe
8 hours ago
$begingroup$
Try to construct two non-congruent triangles with the given quantities—you won’t succeed.
$endgroup$
– Michael Hoppe
8 hours ago
add a comment
|
3 Answers
3
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
Welcome to axiomatic mathematics!
Axioms are accepted not just on the basis of obviousness.
Yes, the truth of this statement should be obvious, as the comment of @MichaelHoppe remarks.
And yes, axioms and other mathematical statements can have a persnickety precision to them which requires you to memorize symbols in order. All I'll say to this is, you memorized your counting numbers once upon a time when you were much much younger, I'm sure you can memorize this axiom.
But the real point about formulating axioms is that they should be as narrowly formulated as possible, subject to the all important restriction that the entire rest of the theory can be derived from the axioms. Mathematicians HATE to accept things without proof. They just HATE it. If they have to accept an axiom, they want it to be formulated as narrowly as possible. In the case of this axiom, the hypotheses are the same as the stronger SAS theorem, but the conclusion is quite a bit narrower: all the conclusion asserts is equality of one specific angle pair.
The point is that from this narrow conclusion, many broader conclusions may be derived. For example, from the narrow conclusion of equality of one angle pair, one may prove equality of the other angle pair, as you have correctly noted in the edit at the bottom of your question. And then one can go on to prove other theorems about triangles such as SSS and so on. All from just one, narrow, very specifically formulated, special version of SAS! A mathematician loves that.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
I have no doubt about the validity of the axiom. But I actually can't make sense of the order of the angles. The first angle is obviously the one between the sides, but the latter one appears random to me.
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
6 hours ago
1
$begingroup$
Well, the triangle only has three angles. Pick one of those two, and formulate your axiom with that one. As I've tried to say, the point is not the validity of the axiom, it is instead the narrowness of its conclusions, and the broadness of its applications.
$endgroup$
– Lee Mosher
5 hours ago
add a comment
|
$begingroup$
I am not sure this is a satisfactory answer.
That assertion is essentially Euclid's Proposition 4 (SAS) in Book I:
If two triangles have two sides equal to two sides respectively, and
have the angles contained by the equal straight lines equal, then they
also have the base equal to the base, the triangle equals the
triangle, and the remaining angles equal the remaining angles
respectively, namely those opposite the equal sides.
The notes on Euclid's proof at
https://mathcs.clarku.edu/~djoyce/java/elements/bookI/propI4.html comment clearly on his use of an essentially undefined notion of congruence based on superimposing one triangle on another.
I suspect the author of your text was sufficiently unhappy with Euclid's argument that they created a new axiom instead, in order to get started on the interesting theorems.
You will probably never need to use it directly as an axiom once you've used it to prove SSS, ASA and SAS.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Still can't figure out the logic behind the equality of the angles ABC and A'B'C'. Do I just randomly pick one of the two remaining angles and say they are equal?
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@DreaDk It seems as if that's what the book's author wants you to accept as an axiom. I don't like it either, but I understand why something like it is necessary in order to get to interesting geometry. Foundations are hard. See Hilbert's axioms at en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hilbert%27s_axioms
$endgroup$
– Ethan Bolker
7 hours ago
add a comment
|
$begingroup$
The assumptions are identical to $SAS$ so why is it an Axiom ? They should be able to prove it from previous theorems.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
It's a weaker version of SAS that we use to prove SAS. This whole thing sounds so arbitrary when I read it.
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
7 hours ago
add a comment
|
Your Answer
StackExchange.ready(function()
var channelOptions =
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
;
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
createEditor();
);
else
createEditor();
);
function createEditor()
StackExchange.prepareEditor(
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader:
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/4.0/"u003ecc by-sa 4.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
,
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
);
);
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3381889%2fcongruence-of-angles-axiom%23new-answer', 'question_page');
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
3 Answers
3
active
oldest
votes
3 Answers
3
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
Welcome to axiomatic mathematics!
Axioms are accepted not just on the basis of obviousness.
Yes, the truth of this statement should be obvious, as the comment of @MichaelHoppe remarks.
And yes, axioms and other mathematical statements can have a persnickety precision to them which requires you to memorize symbols in order. All I'll say to this is, you memorized your counting numbers once upon a time when you were much much younger, I'm sure you can memorize this axiom.
But the real point about formulating axioms is that they should be as narrowly formulated as possible, subject to the all important restriction that the entire rest of the theory can be derived from the axioms. Mathematicians HATE to accept things without proof. They just HATE it. If they have to accept an axiom, they want it to be formulated as narrowly as possible. In the case of this axiom, the hypotheses are the same as the stronger SAS theorem, but the conclusion is quite a bit narrower: all the conclusion asserts is equality of one specific angle pair.
The point is that from this narrow conclusion, many broader conclusions may be derived. For example, from the narrow conclusion of equality of one angle pair, one may prove equality of the other angle pair, as you have correctly noted in the edit at the bottom of your question. And then one can go on to prove other theorems about triangles such as SSS and so on. All from just one, narrow, very specifically formulated, special version of SAS! A mathematician loves that.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
I have no doubt about the validity of the axiom. But I actually can't make sense of the order of the angles. The first angle is obviously the one between the sides, but the latter one appears random to me.
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
6 hours ago
1
$begingroup$
Well, the triangle only has three angles. Pick one of those two, and formulate your axiom with that one. As I've tried to say, the point is not the validity of the axiom, it is instead the narrowness of its conclusions, and the broadness of its applications.
$endgroup$
– Lee Mosher
5 hours ago
add a comment
|
$begingroup$
Welcome to axiomatic mathematics!
Axioms are accepted not just on the basis of obviousness.
Yes, the truth of this statement should be obvious, as the comment of @MichaelHoppe remarks.
And yes, axioms and other mathematical statements can have a persnickety precision to them which requires you to memorize symbols in order. All I'll say to this is, you memorized your counting numbers once upon a time when you were much much younger, I'm sure you can memorize this axiom.
But the real point about formulating axioms is that they should be as narrowly formulated as possible, subject to the all important restriction that the entire rest of the theory can be derived from the axioms. Mathematicians HATE to accept things without proof. They just HATE it. If they have to accept an axiom, they want it to be formulated as narrowly as possible. In the case of this axiom, the hypotheses are the same as the stronger SAS theorem, but the conclusion is quite a bit narrower: all the conclusion asserts is equality of one specific angle pair.
The point is that from this narrow conclusion, many broader conclusions may be derived. For example, from the narrow conclusion of equality of one angle pair, one may prove equality of the other angle pair, as you have correctly noted in the edit at the bottom of your question. And then one can go on to prove other theorems about triangles such as SSS and so on. All from just one, narrow, very specifically formulated, special version of SAS! A mathematician loves that.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
I have no doubt about the validity of the axiom. But I actually can't make sense of the order of the angles. The first angle is obviously the one between the sides, but the latter one appears random to me.
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
6 hours ago
1
$begingroup$
Well, the triangle only has three angles. Pick one of those two, and formulate your axiom with that one. As I've tried to say, the point is not the validity of the axiom, it is instead the narrowness of its conclusions, and the broadness of its applications.
$endgroup$
– Lee Mosher
5 hours ago
add a comment
|
$begingroup$
Welcome to axiomatic mathematics!
Axioms are accepted not just on the basis of obviousness.
Yes, the truth of this statement should be obvious, as the comment of @MichaelHoppe remarks.
And yes, axioms and other mathematical statements can have a persnickety precision to them which requires you to memorize symbols in order. All I'll say to this is, you memorized your counting numbers once upon a time when you were much much younger, I'm sure you can memorize this axiom.
But the real point about formulating axioms is that they should be as narrowly formulated as possible, subject to the all important restriction that the entire rest of the theory can be derived from the axioms. Mathematicians HATE to accept things without proof. They just HATE it. If they have to accept an axiom, they want it to be formulated as narrowly as possible. In the case of this axiom, the hypotheses are the same as the stronger SAS theorem, but the conclusion is quite a bit narrower: all the conclusion asserts is equality of one specific angle pair.
The point is that from this narrow conclusion, many broader conclusions may be derived. For example, from the narrow conclusion of equality of one angle pair, one may prove equality of the other angle pair, as you have correctly noted in the edit at the bottom of your question. And then one can go on to prove other theorems about triangles such as SSS and so on. All from just one, narrow, very specifically formulated, special version of SAS! A mathematician loves that.
$endgroup$
Welcome to axiomatic mathematics!
Axioms are accepted not just on the basis of obviousness.
Yes, the truth of this statement should be obvious, as the comment of @MichaelHoppe remarks.
And yes, axioms and other mathematical statements can have a persnickety precision to them which requires you to memorize symbols in order. All I'll say to this is, you memorized your counting numbers once upon a time when you were much much younger, I'm sure you can memorize this axiom.
But the real point about formulating axioms is that they should be as narrowly formulated as possible, subject to the all important restriction that the entire rest of the theory can be derived from the axioms. Mathematicians HATE to accept things without proof. They just HATE it. If they have to accept an axiom, they want it to be formulated as narrowly as possible. In the case of this axiom, the hypotheses are the same as the stronger SAS theorem, but the conclusion is quite a bit narrower: all the conclusion asserts is equality of one specific angle pair.
The point is that from this narrow conclusion, many broader conclusions may be derived. For example, from the narrow conclusion of equality of one angle pair, one may prove equality of the other angle pair, as you have correctly noted in the edit at the bottom of your question. And then one can go on to prove other theorems about triangles such as SSS and so on. All from just one, narrow, very specifically formulated, special version of SAS! A mathematician loves that.
answered 7 hours ago
Lee MosherLee Mosher
60.4k4 gold badges40 silver badges97 bronze badges
60.4k4 gold badges40 silver badges97 bronze badges
$begingroup$
I have no doubt about the validity of the axiom. But I actually can't make sense of the order of the angles. The first angle is obviously the one between the sides, but the latter one appears random to me.
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
6 hours ago
1
$begingroup$
Well, the triangle only has three angles. Pick one of those two, and formulate your axiom with that one. As I've tried to say, the point is not the validity of the axiom, it is instead the narrowness of its conclusions, and the broadness of its applications.
$endgroup$
– Lee Mosher
5 hours ago
add a comment
|
$begingroup$
I have no doubt about the validity of the axiom. But I actually can't make sense of the order of the angles. The first angle is obviously the one between the sides, but the latter one appears random to me.
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
6 hours ago
1
$begingroup$
Well, the triangle only has three angles. Pick one of those two, and formulate your axiom with that one. As I've tried to say, the point is not the validity of the axiom, it is instead the narrowness of its conclusions, and the broadness of its applications.
$endgroup$
– Lee Mosher
5 hours ago
$begingroup$
I have no doubt about the validity of the axiom. But I actually can't make sense of the order of the angles. The first angle is obviously the one between the sides, but the latter one appears random to me.
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
6 hours ago
$begingroup$
I have no doubt about the validity of the axiom. But I actually can't make sense of the order of the angles. The first angle is obviously the one between the sides, but the latter one appears random to me.
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
6 hours ago
1
1
$begingroup$
Well, the triangle only has three angles. Pick one of those two, and formulate your axiom with that one. As I've tried to say, the point is not the validity of the axiom, it is instead the narrowness of its conclusions, and the broadness of its applications.
$endgroup$
– Lee Mosher
5 hours ago
$begingroup$
Well, the triangle only has three angles. Pick one of those two, and formulate your axiom with that one. As I've tried to say, the point is not the validity of the axiom, it is instead the narrowness of its conclusions, and the broadness of its applications.
$endgroup$
– Lee Mosher
5 hours ago
add a comment
|
$begingroup$
I am not sure this is a satisfactory answer.
That assertion is essentially Euclid's Proposition 4 (SAS) in Book I:
If two triangles have two sides equal to two sides respectively, and
have the angles contained by the equal straight lines equal, then they
also have the base equal to the base, the triangle equals the
triangle, and the remaining angles equal the remaining angles
respectively, namely those opposite the equal sides.
The notes on Euclid's proof at
https://mathcs.clarku.edu/~djoyce/java/elements/bookI/propI4.html comment clearly on his use of an essentially undefined notion of congruence based on superimposing one triangle on another.
I suspect the author of your text was sufficiently unhappy with Euclid's argument that they created a new axiom instead, in order to get started on the interesting theorems.
You will probably never need to use it directly as an axiom once you've used it to prove SSS, ASA and SAS.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Still can't figure out the logic behind the equality of the angles ABC and A'B'C'. Do I just randomly pick one of the two remaining angles and say they are equal?
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@DreaDk It seems as if that's what the book's author wants you to accept as an axiom. I don't like it either, but I understand why something like it is necessary in order to get to interesting geometry. Foundations are hard. See Hilbert's axioms at en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hilbert%27s_axioms
$endgroup$
– Ethan Bolker
7 hours ago
add a comment
|
$begingroup$
I am not sure this is a satisfactory answer.
That assertion is essentially Euclid's Proposition 4 (SAS) in Book I:
If two triangles have two sides equal to two sides respectively, and
have the angles contained by the equal straight lines equal, then they
also have the base equal to the base, the triangle equals the
triangle, and the remaining angles equal the remaining angles
respectively, namely those opposite the equal sides.
The notes on Euclid's proof at
https://mathcs.clarku.edu/~djoyce/java/elements/bookI/propI4.html comment clearly on his use of an essentially undefined notion of congruence based on superimposing one triangle on another.
I suspect the author of your text was sufficiently unhappy with Euclid's argument that they created a new axiom instead, in order to get started on the interesting theorems.
You will probably never need to use it directly as an axiom once you've used it to prove SSS, ASA and SAS.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Still can't figure out the logic behind the equality of the angles ABC and A'B'C'. Do I just randomly pick one of the two remaining angles and say they are equal?
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@DreaDk It seems as if that's what the book's author wants you to accept as an axiom. I don't like it either, but I understand why something like it is necessary in order to get to interesting geometry. Foundations are hard. See Hilbert's axioms at en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hilbert%27s_axioms
$endgroup$
– Ethan Bolker
7 hours ago
add a comment
|
$begingroup$
I am not sure this is a satisfactory answer.
That assertion is essentially Euclid's Proposition 4 (SAS) in Book I:
If two triangles have two sides equal to two sides respectively, and
have the angles contained by the equal straight lines equal, then they
also have the base equal to the base, the triangle equals the
triangle, and the remaining angles equal the remaining angles
respectively, namely those opposite the equal sides.
The notes on Euclid's proof at
https://mathcs.clarku.edu/~djoyce/java/elements/bookI/propI4.html comment clearly on his use of an essentially undefined notion of congruence based on superimposing one triangle on another.
I suspect the author of your text was sufficiently unhappy with Euclid's argument that they created a new axiom instead, in order to get started on the interesting theorems.
You will probably never need to use it directly as an axiom once you've used it to prove SSS, ASA and SAS.
$endgroup$
I am not sure this is a satisfactory answer.
That assertion is essentially Euclid's Proposition 4 (SAS) in Book I:
If two triangles have two sides equal to two sides respectively, and
have the angles contained by the equal straight lines equal, then they
also have the base equal to the base, the triangle equals the
triangle, and the remaining angles equal the remaining angles
respectively, namely those opposite the equal sides.
The notes on Euclid's proof at
https://mathcs.clarku.edu/~djoyce/java/elements/bookI/propI4.html comment clearly on his use of an essentially undefined notion of congruence based on superimposing one triangle on another.
I suspect the author of your text was sufficiently unhappy with Euclid's argument that they created a new axiom instead, in order to get started on the interesting theorems.
You will probably never need to use it directly as an axiom once you've used it to prove SSS, ASA and SAS.
answered 8 hours ago
Ethan BolkerEthan Bolker
56.8k5 gold badges63 silver badges138 bronze badges
56.8k5 gold badges63 silver badges138 bronze badges
$begingroup$
Still can't figure out the logic behind the equality of the angles ABC and A'B'C'. Do I just randomly pick one of the two remaining angles and say they are equal?
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@DreaDk It seems as if that's what the book's author wants you to accept as an axiom. I don't like it either, but I understand why something like it is necessary in order to get to interesting geometry. Foundations are hard. See Hilbert's axioms at en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hilbert%27s_axioms
$endgroup$
– Ethan Bolker
7 hours ago
add a comment
|
$begingroup$
Still can't figure out the logic behind the equality of the angles ABC and A'B'C'. Do I just randomly pick one of the two remaining angles and say they are equal?
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@DreaDk It seems as if that's what the book's author wants you to accept as an axiom. I don't like it either, but I understand why something like it is necessary in order to get to interesting geometry. Foundations are hard. See Hilbert's axioms at en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hilbert%27s_axioms
$endgroup$
– Ethan Bolker
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
Still can't figure out the logic behind the equality of the angles ABC and A'B'C'. Do I just randomly pick one of the two remaining angles and say they are equal?
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
Still can't figure out the logic behind the equality of the angles ABC and A'B'C'. Do I just randomly pick one of the two remaining angles and say they are equal?
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@DreaDk It seems as if that's what the book's author wants you to accept as an axiom. I don't like it either, but I understand why something like it is necessary in order to get to interesting geometry. Foundations are hard. See Hilbert's axioms at en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hilbert%27s_axioms
$endgroup$
– Ethan Bolker
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
@DreaDk It seems as if that's what the book's author wants you to accept as an axiom. I don't like it either, but I understand why something like it is necessary in order to get to interesting geometry. Foundations are hard. See Hilbert's axioms at en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hilbert%27s_axioms
$endgroup$
– Ethan Bolker
7 hours ago
add a comment
|
$begingroup$
The assumptions are identical to $SAS$ so why is it an Axiom ? They should be able to prove it from previous theorems.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
It's a weaker version of SAS that we use to prove SAS. This whole thing sounds so arbitrary when I read it.
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
7 hours ago
add a comment
|
$begingroup$
The assumptions are identical to $SAS$ so why is it an Axiom ? They should be able to prove it from previous theorems.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
It's a weaker version of SAS that we use to prove SAS. This whole thing sounds so arbitrary when I read it.
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
7 hours ago
add a comment
|
$begingroup$
The assumptions are identical to $SAS$ so why is it an Axiom ? They should be able to prove it from previous theorems.
$endgroup$
The assumptions are identical to $SAS$ so why is it an Axiom ? They should be able to prove it from previous theorems.
answered 7 hours ago
Mohammad Riazi-KermaniMohammad Riazi-Kermani
54.4k4 gold badges27 silver badges74 bronze badges
54.4k4 gold badges27 silver badges74 bronze badges
$begingroup$
It's a weaker version of SAS that we use to prove SAS. This whole thing sounds so arbitrary when I read it.
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
7 hours ago
add a comment
|
$begingroup$
It's a weaker version of SAS that we use to prove SAS. This whole thing sounds so arbitrary when I read it.
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
It's a weaker version of SAS that we use to prove SAS. This whole thing sounds so arbitrary when I read it.
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
7 hours ago
$begingroup$
It's a weaker version of SAS that we use to prove SAS. This whole thing sounds so arbitrary when I read it.
$endgroup$
– DreaDk
7 hours ago
add a comment
|
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3381889%2fcongruence-of-angles-axiom%23new-answer', 'question_page');
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
$begingroup$
Try to construct two non-congruent triangles with the given quantities—you won’t succeed.
$endgroup$
– Michael Hoppe
8 hours ago