Alternative Proof of Burnside's LemmaCriteria for Groups and Burnside's LemmaConfusion concerning Burnside's LemmaUsing Burnside's lemma on the cube.Probabilistic Interpretation of Burnside's LemmaBurnside's lemma simple useUnderstanding and applying Burnside's lemmaGroup actions, the Orbit-Stabilizer Theorem and Burnside's Lemma.
How to use grep to search through the --help output?
Why should we care about syntactic proofs if we can show semantically that statements are true?
sed delete all the words before a match
During the Space Shuttle Columbia Disaster of 2003, Why Did The Flight Director Say, "Lock the doors."?
Y2K... in 2019?
Was the 2019 Lion King film made through motion capture?
What is my malfunctioning AI harvesting from humans?
Ordering a word list
(11 of 11: Meta) What is Pyramid Cult's All-Time Favorite?
Why isn’t SHA-3 in wider use?
Dropdowns & Chevrons for Right to Left languages
Dereferencing a pointer in a 'for' loop initializer creates a segmentation fault
How can you evade tax by getting employment income just in equity, then using this equity as collateral to take out loan?
Why doesn't the "ch" pronunciation rule occur for words such as "durch" and "manchmal"?
How to mark beverage cans in a cooler for a blind person?
What are the uses and limitations of Persuasion, Insight, and Deception against other PCs?
Unique combinations of a list of tuples
Blocking people from taking pictures of me with smartphone
Performance of a branch and bound algorithm VS branch-cut-heuristics
Why does Intel's Haswell chip allow FP multiplication to be twice as fast as addition?
Can a spacecraft use an accelerometer to determine its orientation?
How should an administrative assistant reply to student addressing them as "Professor" or "Doctor"?
Why do oscilloscopes use SMPS instead of linear power supply?
Why aren’t emergency services using callsigns?
Alternative Proof of Burnside's Lemma
Criteria for Groups and Burnside's LemmaConfusion concerning Burnside's LemmaUsing Burnside's lemma on the cube.Probabilistic Interpretation of Burnside's LemmaBurnside's lemma simple useUnderstanding and applying Burnside's lemmaGroup actions, the Orbit-Stabilizer Theorem and Burnside's Lemma.
.everyoneloves__top-leaderboard:empty,.everyoneloves__mid-leaderboard:empty,.everyoneloves__bot-mid-leaderboard:empty margin-bottom:0;
$begingroup$
I studied group theory a long time ago. Back then, I didn't understand how to use the group theory-specific idioms to write short proofs. I still don't.
Below is a proof of Burnside's Lemma using as little group theory as possible, by which I mean it uses few commonly-known lemmas. The basic thrust of the argument is showing that both sides count the number of fixed points of $varphi(g)$ for each $g$ in the group $G$ .
What are some good ways of proving Burnside's lemma without spending much ink and idiomatically using other results that are "more basic" than Burnside's Lemma?
I'm attaching below my proof of the lemma. I looked at Wikipedia to get the statement of the theorem, but did not read the proof section until I completed the proof.
Proof of Burnside's lemma.
First a word on notation.
The notation $[psi]$ for a proposition $psi$ is $1$ if the expression is true and $0$ if the expression is false. It is called an Iverson bracket.
A group $G$ acts on a set $X$ . Equivalently, there exists a function $varphi : G to (X to X) $ that sends each $g$ to a function from $X$ to itself. $varphi$ is not required to be injective. $varphi$ is not completely arbitrary; it satisfies some laws that I won't enumerate here.
Let $langle g, x rangle$ denote the group action.
$$ langle g,x rangle stackrelmathrmdef= (, varphi(g),)(x) $$
Let $G(x)$ denote the orbit of $x$ in $G$ .
$$ G(x) stackrelmathrmdef= g in G ; $$
Let $simeq_G$ be a binary predicate that is true if and only if there exists a $g$ that sends the left argument to the right argument.
$$ x simeq_G y stackrelmathrmdefiff left(exists g in G mathop. langle g, x rangle = y right) $$
Note that
$$ x simeq_G y iff x in G(y) $$
and
$$ x simeq_G y iff y in G(x) $$
Let's show that the negation of Burnside's Lemma is absurd.
$$ |X/G|cdot|G| ne sum_g in G |X^g| $$
$$ |X/G|cdot|G| ne sum_g in G left|left langle g, x rangle = x rightright| $$
$$ |X/G|cdot|G| ne sum_g in Gsum_x in X [langle g, x rangle = x ] $$
$$ |G|cdot|X/G| ne sum_g in Gsum_x in X [langle g, x rangle = x ] $$
$$ |G|cdotsum_x in X frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in X [langle g, x rangle = x ] $$
$$ |G|cdotsum_x in X frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ][ x = y ] $$
If we relax the restriction that $x = y$ and insist instead that $x simeq_G y$, then we can count each $x$ at $frac1G(x) = frac1$ value.
$$ |G|cdotsum_x in X frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac[x simeq_G y]G(x) $$
However, the condition $x simeq_G y$ is redundant if we already know that $langle g, x rangle = y$ for some particular $g in G$ .
$$ |G|cdotsum_x in X frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
$$ sum_x in X |G| cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
Replace $|G|$ with a sum counting $1$ for each item in $G$.
$$ sum_x in X left( sum_g in G 1 right) cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
The group element $g$ acting on the set $X$ sends a particular $x in X$ to exactly one destination.
$$ sum_x in X left( sum_g in G sum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y] right) cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
$$ sum_x in X sum_g in G sum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y] cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
All sub-expressions are positive, we can reorder.
$$ sum_g in G sum_x in X sum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y] cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
$$ bot $$
Therefore $ | X/ G | cdot |G| = sum_g in G |X^g| $ as desired.
group-theory alternative-proof
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I studied group theory a long time ago. Back then, I didn't understand how to use the group theory-specific idioms to write short proofs. I still don't.
Below is a proof of Burnside's Lemma using as little group theory as possible, by which I mean it uses few commonly-known lemmas. The basic thrust of the argument is showing that both sides count the number of fixed points of $varphi(g)$ for each $g$ in the group $G$ .
What are some good ways of proving Burnside's lemma without spending much ink and idiomatically using other results that are "more basic" than Burnside's Lemma?
I'm attaching below my proof of the lemma. I looked at Wikipedia to get the statement of the theorem, but did not read the proof section until I completed the proof.
Proof of Burnside's lemma.
First a word on notation.
The notation $[psi]$ for a proposition $psi$ is $1$ if the expression is true and $0$ if the expression is false. It is called an Iverson bracket.
A group $G$ acts on a set $X$ . Equivalently, there exists a function $varphi : G to (X to X) $ that sends each $g$ to a function from $X$ to itself. $varphi$ is not required to be injective. $varphi$ is not completely arbitrary; it satisfies some laws that I won't enumerate here.
Let $langle g, x rangle$ denote the group action.
$$ langle g,x rangle stackrelmathrmdef= (, varphi(g),)(x) $$
Let $G(x)$ denote the orbit of $x$ in $G$ .
$$ G(x) stackrelmathrmdef= g in G ; $$
Let $simeq_G$ be a binary predicate that is true if and only if there exists a $g$ that sends the left argument to the right argument.
$$ x simeq_G y stackrelmathrmdefiff left(exists g in G mathop. langle g, x rangle = y right) $$
Note that
$$ x simeq_G y iff x in G(y) $$
and
$$ x simeq_G y iff y in G(x) $$
Let's show that the negation of Burnside's Lemma is absurd.
$$ |X/G|cdot|G| ne sum_g in G |X^g| $$
$$ |X/G|cdot|G| ne sum_g in G left|left langle g, x rangle = x rightright| $$
$$ |X/G|cdot|G| ne sum_g in Gsum_x in X [langle g, x rangle = x ] $$
$$ |G|cdot|X/G| ne sum_g in Gsum_x in X [langle g, x rangle = x ] $$
$$ |G|cdotsum_x in X frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in X [langle g, x rangle = x ] $$
$$ |G|cdotsum_x in X frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ][ x = y ] $$
If we relax the restriction that $x = y$ and insist instead that $x simeq_G y$, then we can count each $x$ at $frac1G(x) = frac1$ value.
$$ |G|cdotsum_x in X frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac[x simeq_G y]G(x) $$
However, the condition $x simeq_G y$ is redundant if we already know that $langle g, x rangle = y$ for some particular $g in G$ .
$$ |G|cdotsum_x in X frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
$$ sum_x in X |G| cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
Replace $|G|$ with a sum counting $1$ for each item in $G$.
$$ sum_x in X left( sum_g in G 1 right) cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
The group element $g$ acting on the set $X$ sends a particular $x in X$ to exactly one destination.
$$ sum_x in X left( sum_g in G sum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y] right) cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
$$ sum_x in X sum_g in G sum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y] cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
All sub-expressions are positive, we can reorder.
$$ sum_g in G sum_x in X sum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y] cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
$$ bot $$
Therefore $ | X/ G | cdot |G| = sum_g in G |X^g| $ as desired.
group-theory alternative-proof
$endgroup$
1
$begingroup$
Just as a style convention, it is somewhat confusing to write a proof using contradiction when your argument does not really rely on contradiction! A lot of beginning proof writers fall into the pitfall of using the following style: They want to show P is true. Then they assume P is not true. Then by using a direct argument, they show P is true and then claim it is a contradiction... but they aren't really contradicting anything! Therefore, it is more clear to write things directly. See if you can do that here by using the same proof to show |X/G|*|G| = sum |X^g| directly
$endgroup$
– Sandeep Silwal
8 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I studied group theory a long time ago. Back then, I didn't understand how to use the group theory-specific idioms to write short proofs. I still don't.
Below is a proof of Burnside's Lemma using as little group theory as possible, by which I mean it uses few commonly-known lemmas. The basic thrust of the argument is showing that both sides count the number of fixed points of $varphi(g)$ for each $g$ in the group $G$ .
What are some good ways of proving Burnside's lemma without spending much ink and idiomatically using other results that are "more basic" than Burnside's Lemma?
I'm attaching below my proof of the lemma. I looked at Wikipedia to get the statement of the theorem, but did not read the proof section until I completed the proof.
Proof of Burnside's lemma.
First a word on notation.
The notation $[psi]$ for a proposition $psi$ is $1$ if the expression is true and $0$ if the expression is false. It is called an Iverson bracket.
A group $G$ acts on a set $X$ . Equivalently, there exists a function $varphi : G to (X to X) $ that sends each $g$ to a function from $X$ to itself. $varphi$ is not required to be injective. $varphi$ is not completely arbitrary; it satisfies some laws that I won't enumerate here.
Let $langle g, x rangle$ denote the group action.
$$ langle g,x rangle stackrelmathrmdef= (, varphi(g),)(x) $$
Let $G(x)$ denote the orbit of $x$ in $G$ .
$$ G(x) stackrelmathrmdef= g in G ; $$
Let $simeq_G$ be a binary predicate that is true if and only if there exists a $g$ that sends the left argument to the right argument.
$$ x simeq_G y stackrelmathrmdefiff left(exists g in G mathop. langle g, x rangle = y right) $$
Note that
$$ x simeq_G y iff x in G(y) $$
and
$$ x simeq_G y iff y in G(x) $$
Let's show that the negation of Burnside's Lemma is absurd.
$$ |X/G|cdot|G| ne sum_g in G |X^g| $$
$$ |X/G|cdot|G| ne sum_g in G left|left langle g, x rangle = x rightright| $$
$$ |X/G|cdot|G| ne sum_g in Gsum_x in X [langle g, x rangle = x ] $$
$$ |G|cdot|X/G| ne sum_g in Gsum_x in X [langle g, x rangle = x ] $$
$$ |G|cdotsum_x in X frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in X [langle g, x rangle = x ] $$
$$ |G|cdotsum_x in X frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ][ x = y ] $$
If we relax the restriction that $x = y$ and insist instead that $x simeq_G y$, then we can count each $x$ at $frac1G(x) = frac1$ value.
$$ |G|cdotsum_x in X frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac[x simeq_G y]G(x) $$
However, the condition $x simeq_G y$ is redundant if we already know that $langle g, x rangle = y$ for some particular $g in G$ .
$$ |G|cdotsum_x in X frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
$$ sum_x in X |G| cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
Replace $|G|$ with a sum counting $1$ for each item in $G$.
$$ sum_x in X left( sum_g in G 1 right) cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
The group element $g$ acting on the set $X$ sends a particular $x in X$ to exactly one destination.
$$ sum_x in X left( sum_g in G sum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y] right) cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
$$ sum_x in X sum_g in G sum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y] cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
All sub-expressions are positive, we can reorder.
$$ sum_g in G sum_x in X sum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y] cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
$$ bot $$
Therefore $ | X/ G | cdot |G| = sum_g in G |X^g| $ as desired.
group-theory alternative-proof
$endgroup$
I studied group theory a long time ago. Back then, I didn't understand how to use the group theory-specific idioms to write short proofs. I still don't.
Below is a proof of Burnside's Lemma using as little group theory as possible, by which I mean it uses few commonly-known lemmas. The basic thrust of the argument is showing that both sides count the number of fixed points of $varphi(g)$ for each $g$ in the group $G$ .
What are some good ways of proving Burnside's lemma without spending much ink and idiomatically using other results that are "more basic" than Burnside's Lemma?
I'm attaching below my proof of the lemma. I looked at Wikipedia to get the statement of the theorem, but did not read the proof section until I completed the proof.
Proof of Burnside's lemma.
First a word on notation.
The notation $[psi]$ for a proposition $psi$ is $1$ if the expression is true and $0$ if the expression is false. It is called an Iverson bracket.
A group $G$ acts on a set $X$ . Equivalently, there exists a function $varphi : G to (X to X) $ that sends each $g$ to a function from $X$ to itself. $varphi$ is not required to be injective. $varphi$ is not completely arbitrary; it satisfies some laws that I won't enumerate here.
Let $langle g, x rangle$ denote the group action.
$$ langle g,x rangle stackrelmathrmdef= (, varphi(g),)(x) $$
Let $G(x)$ denote the orbit of $x$ in $G$ .
$$ G(x) stackrelmathrmdef= g in G ; $$
Let $simeq_G$ be a binary predicate that is true if and only if there exists a $g$ that sends the left argument to the right argument.
$$ x simeq_G y stackrelmathrmdefiff left(exists g in G mathop. langle g, x rangle = y right) $$
Note that
$$ x simeq_G y iff x in G(y) $$
and
$$ x simeq_G y iff y in G(x) $$
Let's show that the negation of Burnside's Lemma is absurd.
$$ |X/G|cdot|G| ne sum_g in G |X^g| $$
$$ |X/G|cdot|G| ne sum_g in G left|left langle g, x rangle = x rightright| $$
$$ |X/G|cdot|G| ne sum_g in Gsum_x in X [langle g, x rangle = x ] $$
$$ |G|cdot|X/G| ne sum_g in Gsum_x in X [langle g, x rangle = x ] $$
$$ |G|cdotsum_x in X frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in X [langle g, x rangle = x ] $$
$$ |G|cdotsum_x in X frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ][ x = y ] $$
If we relax the restriction that $x = y$ and insist instead that $x simeq_G y$, then we can count each $x$ at $frac1G(x) = frac1$ value.
$$ |G|cdotsum_x in X frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac[x simeq_G y]G(x) $$
However, the condition $x simeq_G y$ is redundant if we already know that $langle g, x rangle = y$ for some particular $g in G$ .
$$ |G|cdotsum_x in X frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
$$ sum_x in X |G| cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
Replace $|G|$ with a sum counting $1$ for each item in $G$.
$$ sum_x in X left( sum_g in G 1 right) cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
The group element $g$ acting on the set $X$ sends a particular $x in X$ to exactly one destination.
$$ sum_x in X left( sum_g in G sum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y] right) cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
$$ sum_x in X sum_g in G sum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y] cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
All sub-expressions are positive, we can reorder.
$$ sum_g in G sum_x in X sum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y] cdot frac1G(x) ne sum_g in Gsum_x in Xsum_y in X [langle g, x rangle = y ]cdotfrac1G(x) $$
$$ bot $$
Therefore $ | X/ G | cdot |G| = sum_g in G |X^g| $ as desired.
group-theory alternative-proof
group-theory alternative-proof
asked 8 hours ago
Gregory NisbetGregory Nisbet
1,0458 silver badges13 bronze badges
1,0458 silver badges13 bronze badges
1
$begingroup$
Just as a style convention, it is somewhat confusing to write a proof using contradiction when your argument does not really rely on contradiction! A lot of beginning proof writers fall into the pitfall of using the following style: They want to show P is true. Then they assume P is not true. Then by using a direct argument, they show P is true and then claim it is a contradiction... but they aren't really contradicting anything! Therefore, it is more clear to write things directly. See if you can do that here by using the same proof to show |X/G|*|G| = sum |X^g| directly
$endgroup$
– Sandeep Silwal
8 hours ago
add a comment |
1
$begingroup$
Just as a style convention, it is somewhat confusing to write a proof using contradiction when your argument does not really rely on contradiction! A lot of beginning proof writers fall into the pitfall of using the following style: They want to show P is true. Then they assume P is not true. Then by using a direct argument, they show P is true and then claim it is a contradiction... but they aren't really contradicting anything! Therefore, it is more clear to write things directly. See if you can do that here by using the same proof to show |X/G|*|G| = sum |X^g| directly
$endgroup$
– Sandeep Silwal
8 hours ago
1
1
$begingroup$
Just as a style convention, it is somewhat confusing to write a proof using contradiction when your argument does not really rely on contradiction! A lot of beginning proof writers fall into the pitfall of using the following style: They want to show P is true. Then they assume P is not true. Then by using a direct argument, they show P is true and then claim it is a contradiction... but they aren't really contradicting anything! Therefore, it is more clear to write things directly. See if you can do that here by using the same proof to show |X/G|*|G| = sum |X^g| directly
$endgroup$
– Sandeep Silwal
8 hours ago
$begingroup$
Just as a style convention, it is somewhat confusing to write a proof using contradiction when your argument does not really rely on contradiction! A lot of beginning proof writers fall into the pitfall of using the following style: They want to show P is true. Then they assume P is not true. Then by using a direct argument, they show P is true and then claim it is a contradiction... but they aren't really contradicting anything! Therefore, it is more clear to write things directly. See if you can do that here by using the same proof to show |X/G|*|G| = sum |X^g| directly
$endgroup$
– Sandeep Silwal
8 hours ago
add a comment |
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
Hint:
Prescribe function $chi:Gtimes Xto mathbb0,1$ by stating that: $$chi(g,x)=1iff gx=x$$ Then automatically $chi(g,x)=0$ if $gxneq x$.
Then the theorem of Burnside will show up if we work out the equality:$$frac1sum_gin Gsum_xin Xchi(g,x)=frac1sum_xin Xsum_gin Gchi(g,x)$$
Give it a try.
edit:
Essential for working out the RHS is the following observation.
If $mathcalP$ denotes a partition of finite set $X$ and for every
$x$ the $PinmathcalP$ with $xin P$ is denoted as $left[xright]$
then: $$sum_xin Xfrac1left[xright]=sum_pinmathcalPsum_xin Pfrac1left[xright]=sum_pinmathcalP1=left|mathcalPright|$$
$endgroup$
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ready(function()
var channelOptions =
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
;
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
createEditor();
);
else
createEditor();
);
function createEditor()
StackExchange.prepareEditor(
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader:
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
,
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
);
);
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3319477%2falternative-proof-of-burnsides-lemma%23new-answer', 'question_page');
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
Hint:
Prescribe function $chi:Gtimes Xto mathbb0,1$ by stating that: $$chi(g,x)=1iff gx=x$$ Then automatically $chi(g,x)=0$ if $gxneq x$.
Then the theorem of Burnside will show up if we work out the equality:$$frac1sum_gin Gsum_xin Xchi(g,x)=frac1sum_xin Xsum_gin Gchi(g,x)$$
Give it a try.
edit:
Essential for working out the RHS is the following observation.
If $mathcalP$ denotes a partition of finite set $X$ and for every
$x$ the $PinmathcalP$ with $xin P$ is denoted as $left[xright]$
then: $$sum_xin Xfrac1left[xright]=sum_pinmathcalPsum_xin Pfrac1left[xright]=sum_pinmathcalP1=left|mathcalPright|$$
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Hint:
Prescribe function $chi:Gtimes Xto mathbb0,1$ by stating that: $$chi(g,x)=1iff gx=x$$ Then automatically $chi(g,x)=0$ if $gxneq x$.
Then the theorem of Burnside will show up if we work out the equality:$$frac1sum_gin Gsum_xin Xchi(g,x)=frac1sum_xin Xsum_gin Gchi(g,x)$$
Give it a try.
edit:
Essential for working out the RHS is the following observation.
If $mathcalP$ denotes a partition of finite set $X$ and for every
$x$ the $PinmathcalP$ with $xin P$ is denoted as $left[xright]$
then: $$sum_xin Xfrac1left[xright]=sum_pinmathcalPsum_xin Pfrac1left[xright]=sum_pinmathcalP1=left|mathcalPright|$$
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Hint:
Prescribe function $chi:Gtimes Xto mathbb0,1$ by stating that: $$chi(g,x)=1iff gx=x$$ Then automatically $chi(g,x)=0$ if $gxneq x$.
Then the theorem of Burnside will show up if we work out the equality:$$frac1sum_gin Gsum_xin Xchi(g,x)=frac1sum_xin Xsum_gin Gchi(g,x)$$
Give it a try.
edit:
Essential for working out the RHS is the following observation.
If $mathcalP$ denotes a partition of finite set $X$ and for every
$x$ the $PinmathcalP$ with $xin P$ is denoted as $left[xright]$
then: $$sum_xin Xfrac1left[xright]=sum_pinmathcalPsum_xin Pfrac1left[xright]=sum_pinmathcalP1=left|mathcalPright|$$
$endgroup$
Hint:
Prescribe function $chi:Gtimes Xto mathbb0,1$ by stating that: $$chi(g,x)=1iff gx=x$$ Then automatically $chi(g,x)=0$ if $gxneq x$.
Then the theorem of Burnside will show up if we work out the equality:$$frac1sum_gin Gsum_xin Xchi(g,x)=frac1sum_xin Xsum_gin Gchi(g,x)$$
Give it a try.
edit:
Essential for working out the RHS is the following observation.
If $mathcalP$ denotes a partition of finite set $X$ and for every
$x$ the $PinmathcalP$ with $xin P$ is denoted as $left[xright]$
then: $$sum_xin Xfrac1left[xright]=sum_pinmathcalPsum_xin Pfrac1left[xright]=sum_pinmathcalP1=left|mathcalPright|$$
edited 6 hours ago
answered 7 hours ago
drhabdrhab
111k5 gold badges49 silver badges140 bronze badges
111k5 gold badges49 silver badges140 bronze badges
add a comment |
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3319477%2falternative-proof-of-burnsides-lemma%23new-answer', 'question_page');
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
1
$begingroup$
Just as a style convention, it is somewhat confusing to write a proof using contradiction when your argument does not really rely on contradiction! A lot of beginning proof writers fall into the pitfall of using the following style: They want to show P is true. Then they assume P is not true. Then by using a direct argument, they show P is true and then claim it is a contradiction... but they aren't really contradicting anything! Therefore, it is more clear to write things directly. See if you can do that here by using the same proof to show |X/G|*|G| = sum |X^g| directly
$endgroup$
– Sandeep Silwal
8 hours ago