Is the Münchhausen trilemma really a trilemma?Why is the Münchhausen trilemma an unsolved problem?Is knowledge really related to propositional modal logic?Relation between an argument and false premise on KnowledgeDoes the second Gettier case really work?Is Objective Reality really just the Subjective Agreement of a given group?Can the correspondence theory of truth really be completely avoided?When taking the axiomatic approach to the Munchausen Trilemma, how do you know something is an axiom?Is Quine's epistemology really just a linguistic reinterpretation of Kant's?Are all Informal Logic really just Formal Logic in disguise?Is evolutionary “morality” really the same thing as human morality?

how slow a car engine can run

Why don't commercial aircraft adopt a slightly more seaplane-like design to allow safer ditching in case of emergency?

What is the difference between a Hosaka, Ono-Sendai, and a "deck"?

Why is Google approaching my VPS machine?

How can electric field be defined as force per charge, if the charge makes its own, singular electric field?

Credit card details stolen every 1-2 years. What am I doing wrong?

What are the basics of commands in Minecraft Java Edition?

what relax command means?

Is passive Investigation essentially truesight against illusions?

What does it actually mean to have two time dimensions?

Sending a photo of my bank account card to the future employer

Is this Android phone Android 9.0 or Android 6.0?

How would you say "Sorry, that was a mistake on my part"?

How to honestly answer questions from a girlfriend like "How did you find this place" without giving the impression I'm always talking about my exes?

Why did Steve Rogers choose this character in Endgame?

Is straight-up writing someone's opinions telling?

When designing an adventure, how can I ensure a continuous player experience in a setting that's likely to favor TPKs?

Interviewing with an unmentioned 9 months of sick leave taken during a job

How Can I Process Untrusted Data Sources Securely?

Why does "git status" show I'm on the master branch and "git branch" does not in a newly created repository?

What are "full piece" and "half piece" in chess?

How could an animal "smell" carbon monoxide?

Optimising the Selection of MaxValue in Association

FPGA CPUs, how to find the max speed?



Is the Münchhausen trilemma really a trilemma?


Why is the Münchhausen trilemma an unsolved problem?Is knowledge really related to propositional modal logic?Relation between an argument and false premise on KnowledgeDoes the second Gettier case really work?Is Objective Reality really just the Subjective Agreement of a given group?Can the correspondence theory of truth really be completely avoided?When taking the axiomatic approach to the Munchausen Trilemma, how do you know something is an axiom?Is Quine's epistemology really just a linguistic reinterpretation of Kant's?Are all Informal Logic really just Formal Logic in disguise?Is evolutionary “morality” really the same thing as human morality?






.everyoneloves__top-leaderboard:empty,.everyoneloves__mid-leaderboard:empty,.everyoneloves__bot-mid-leaderboard:empty margin-bottom:0;








2















It claims there are three options of which none of them are satisfying.



Circular argument doesn't prove anything because it's just when the premise is the same as the conclusion.



x ∵ x


Infinite Regress isn't clear on why we'd need to do this let alone even possible to implement so it also has no proofs.



x ∵ ... (never ending chain)


Foundationalism is different in that it's actually useful. Mathematics is it's epitome. Math has tons of proofs. Math isn't only cohesive but also adhesive. What more do we want?



y ∵ x; where x is presumably true


As for it's criticism: Why start at claim x?



Because presumably, it's either true (or hopefully true via self-evidence or empirical research) or it doesn't matter because sometimes we only want to see where the premise takes us.



Maybe an interesting take on my question is: how do we know it's a trilemma?










share|improve this question









New contributor



user40358 is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.














  • 1





    We do not need to "really know", it is an argument against those who claim that we can know (typically, foundationalsts), so their premises are accepted for the purposes of reductio. And those are more than enough to make an exhaustive list of alternatives, however it is itemized. Agrippa's version had 5 items instead of 3.

    – Conifold
    8 hours ago












  • As a consideration... sometimes we don't want to see where the premise takes us. Following a premise takes time and effort. While mathematics may have taken an approach which rewards foundationalism, it can be disconcerting in other disciplines, such as martial arts, where there's a distinct possibility that your entire martial art was founded on an assumption that was wrong. People who arrive at that conclusion often feel like they've wasted 10 or 20 years on an art.

    – Cort Ammon
    6 hours ago

















2















It claims there are three options of which none of them are satisfying.



Circular argument doesn't prove anything because it's just when the premise is the same as the conclusion.



x ∵ x


Infinite Regress isn't clear on why we'd need to do this let alone even possible to implement so it also has no proofs.



x ∵ ... (never ending chain)


Foundationalism is different in that it's actually useful. Mathematics is it's epitome. Math has tons of proofs. Math isn't only cohesive but also adhesive. What more do we want?



y ∵ x; where x is presumably true


As for it's criticism: Why start at claim x?



Because presumably, it's either true (or hopefully true via self-evidence or empirical research) or it doesn't matter because sometimes we only want to see where the premise takes us.



Maybe an interesting take on my question is: how do we know it's a trilemma?










share|improve this question









New contributor



user40358 is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.














  • 1





    We do not need to "really know", it is an argument against those who claim that we can know (typically, foundationalsts), so their premises are accepted for the purposes of reductio. And those are more than enough to make an exhaustive list of alternatives, however it is itemized. Agrippa's version had 5 items instead of 3.

    – Conifold
    8 hours ago












  • As a consideration... sometimes we don't want to see where the premise takes us. Following a premise takes time and effort. While mathematics may have taken an approach which rewards foundationalism, it can be disconcerting in other disciplines, such as martial arts, where there's a distinct possibility that your entire martial art was founded on an assumption that was wrong. People who arrive at that conclusion often feel like they've wasted 10 or 20 years on an art.

    – Cort Ammon
    6 hours ago













2












2








2








It claims there are three options of which none of them are satisfying.



Circular argument doesn't prove anything because it's just when the premise is the same as the conclusion.



x ∵ x


Infinite Regress isn't clear on why we'd need to do this let alone even possible to implement so it also has no proofs.



x ∵ ... (never ending chain)


Foundationalism is different in that it's actually useful. Mathematics is it's epitome. Math has tons of proofs. Math isn't only cohesive but also adhesive. What more do we want?



y ∵ x; where x is presumably true


As for it's criticism: Why start at claim x?



Because presumably, it's either true (or hopefully true via self-evidence or empirical research) or it doesn't matter because sometimes we only want to see where the premise takes us.



Maybe an interesting take on my question is: how do we know it's a trilemma?










share|improve this question









New contributor



user40358 is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.











It claims there are three options of which none of them are satisfying.



Circular argument doesn't prove anything because it's just when the premise is the same as the conclusion.



x ∵ x


Infinite Regress isn't clear on why we'd need to do this let alone even possible to implement so it also has no proofs.



x ∵ ... (never ending chain)


Foundationalism is different in that it's actually useful. Mathematics is it's epitome. Math has tons of proofs. Math isn't only cohesive but also adhesive. What more do we want?



y ∵ x; where x is presumably true


As for it's criticism: Why start at claim x?



Because presumably, it's either true (or hopefully true via self-evidence or empirical research) or it doesn't matter because sometimes we only want to see where the premise takes us.



Maybe an interesting take on my question is: how do we know it's a trilemma?







epistemology foundationalism






share|improve this question









New contributor



user40358 is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.










share|improve this question









New contributor



user40358 is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.








share|improve this question




share|improve this question








edited 6 hours ago







user40358













New contributor



user40358 is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.








asked 9 hours ago









user40358user40358

3131 gold badge2 silver badges6 bronze badges




3131 gold badge2 silver badges6 bronze badges




New contributor



user40358 is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.




New contributor




user40358 is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.









  • 1





    We do not need to "really know", it is an argument against those who claim that we can know (typically, foundationalsts), so their premises are accepted for the purposes of reductio. And those are more than enough to make an exhaustive list of alternatives, however it is itemized. Agrippa's version had 5 items instead of 3.

    – Conifold
    8 hours ago












  • As a consideration... sometimes we don't want to see where the premise takes us. Following a premise takes time and effort. While mathematics may have taken an approach which rewards foundationalism, it can be disconcerting in other disciplines, such as martial arts, where there's a distinct possibility that your entire martial art was founded on an assumption that was wrong. People who arrive at that conclusion often feel like they've wasted 10 or 20 years on an art.

    – Cort Ammon
    6 hours ago












  • 1





    We do not need to "really know", it is an argument against those who claim that we can know (typically, foundationalsts), so their premises are accepted for the purposes of reductio. And those are more than enough to make an exhaustive list of alternatives, however it is itemized. Agrippa's version had 5 items instead of 3.

    – Conifold
    8 hours ago












  • As a consideration... sometimes we don't want to see where the premise takes us. Following a premise takes time and effort. While mathematics may have taken an approach which rewards foundationalism, it can be disconcerting in other disciplines, such as martial arts, where there's a distinct possibility that your entire martial art was founded on an assumption that was wrong. People who arrive at that conclusion often feel like they've wasted 10 or 20 years on an art.

    – Cort Ammon
    6 hours ago







1




1





We do not need to "really know", it is an argument against those who claim that we can know (typically, foundationalsts), so their premises are accepted for the purposes of reductio. And those are more than enough to make an exhaustive list of alternatives, however it is itemized. Agrippa's version had 5 items instead of 3.

– Conifold
8 hours ago






We do not need to "really know", it is an argument against those who claim that we can know (typically, foundationalsts), so their premises are accepted for the purposes of reductio. And those are more than enough to make an exhaustive list of alternatives, however it is itemized. Agrippa's version had 5 items instead of 3.

– Conifold
8 hours ago














As a consideration... sometimes we don't want to see where the premise takes us. Following a premise takes time and effort. While mathematics may have taken an approach which rewards foundationalism, it can be disconcerting in other disciplines, such as martial arts, where there's a distinct possibility that your entire martial art was founded on an assumption that was wrong. People who arrive at that conclusion often feel like they've wasted 10 or 20 years on an art.

– Cort Ammon
6 hours ago





As a consideration... sometimes we don't want to see where the premise takes us. Following a premise takes time and effort. While mathematics may have taken an approach which rewards foundationalism, it can be disconcerting in other disciplines, such as martial arts, where there's a distinct possibility that your entire martial art was founded on an assumption that was wrong. People who arrive at that conclusion often feel like they've wasted 10 or 20 years on an art.

– Cort Ammon
6 hours ago










3 Answers
3






active

oldest

votes


















2














The trilemma is about justification of a given proposition. Any justification, so the story goes, takes ultimately one of these forms if faced with skepticism.



Therefore, the third option is about people who answer to the question "But how do you know that x really is true" dogmatically, e.g. with "Because it is", "Because I say so", etc.



Ultimately, the answers "It is self-evident" and "Empirical research shows it" are, if taken as an end-point of justification, arbitrary since the skeptical objections "Why do you assume self-evidence here, I do not follow" and "What are the standards of this research, why should this be a particularly good standard for the truth of the proposition" are still valid.



Sure, we accept that for statements about the world, empirical research is probably the gold standard and brings us as close to the truth as we might get, but that's not the setting in which the trilemma is supposed to work.



It is about forms of justification, and ending the chain of justification at an arbitrary point is dogmatic, no matter how well-justified the point itself might be. If I claim that this justification was unquestionable and ultimately justifies the whole chain as true, I am dogmatic.






share|improve this answer






























    2














    Circular argument



    We know it's a trilemma because the argument is founded on logic and proofs, and all proofs will end in either circular logic, infinite regression, or a foundational assumption.



    Infinite regress



    You can always break a proof into parts. Those parts get simpler and simpler. Keep breaking them up long enough, and all parts will eventually become circular logic, infinite regression, or foundational assumptions.



    Foundational assumptions



    We know it's a trilemma.




    All kidding aside, we find this pattern is generally true. Logical arguments end up in one of these buckets. Sometimes you can change which bucket it ends up in (such as calculus, which permits us to replace some infinite regression arguments like Zeno's paradox with foundational assumptions about how limits behave), but they end up in one of these buckets in the end.



    The main value of the trilemma is to provoke thought. Its to make you think about what must come of rational thought. If it does so, then it has done its job. Proving it "right" however, is more difficult. The whole point of the trilemma is that people who believe in it are not satisfied with the result of any attempt at a proof.



    To prove it, you would have to select what concept of "proof" you wish to explore and what tools you are willing to consider in the proof thereof. Those are rather personal, which means there's not a one size fits all answer, besides the satirical version I wrote above.



    I would argue that you have a clear opinion as to what proofs you find appealing. You appear to find the foundational ones appealing while the others feel like "not an argument." Consider, however, the infamous Turtles argument:




    The following anecdote is told of William James. [...] After a lecture on
    cosmology and the structure of the solar system, James was accosted by
    a little old lady.



    "Your theory that the sun is the centre of the solar system, and the
    earth is a ball which rotates around it has a very convincing ring to
    it, Mr. James, but it's wrong. I've got a better theory," said the
    little old lady.



    "And what is that, madam?" inquired James politely.



    "That we live on a crust of earth which is on the back of a giant
    turtle."



    Not wishing to demolish this absurd little theory by bringing to bear
    the masses of scientific evidence he had at his command, James decided
    to gently dissuade his opponent by making her see some of the
    inadequacies of her position.



    "If your theory is correct, madam," he asked, "what does this turtle
    stand on?"



    "You're a very clever man, Mr. James, and that's a very good
    question," replied the little old lady, "but I have an answer to it.
    And it's this: The first turtle stands on the back of a second, far
    larger, turtle, who stands directly under him."



    "But what does this second turtle stand on?" persisted James
    patiently.



    To this, the little old lady crowed triumphantly,



    "It's no use, Mr. James—it's turtles all the way down."




    Now you don't have to agree with the opinions in this story, but you must admit that there something worth calling a "proof" here, and it ends in infinite regress. As a thought experiment, how would you go about responding to this? Would you be inclined to tell the little old lady that it is not valid to use infinite regression in proofs?



    Consider how we model numbers with Peano arithmetic. We always have an axiom of induction. We may call that simply a foundational axiom, but if we look into why we think it is a valid axiom, it starts to look an aweful lot like an infinite regression argument. We just tucked it away inside a foundational axiom so that we didn't have to worry about it polluting the rest of the proofs. So, perhaps, in a way, such fundamentals of arithemtic simply prove that infinite regress is a valid method of proof in some carefully constructed circumstances!






    share|improve this answer






























      1














      You have misunderstood the point of the Munchausen Trilemma. It plays a key role in the process of philopshy showing that none of our beliefs are justified knowledge, per the standards of "reasoning".



      Most people hold that they have knowledge and beliefs based on justified reasons, and that beliefs SHOULD be justified, and knowledge isn't knowledge unless it is justified somehow. The term for this is the Principle of Sufficient Reason: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sufficient-reason/



      In its first usage, by Spinoza and Leibniz, the PSR basically called for a proof, before one could satisfy it.



      Another key term in the history of knowledge is Justified True Belief -- the criteria that knowledge is only knowledge if one has both justifications, AND it is true. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-analysis/



      However, most empiricists since Locke have been indirect realists -- holding that the world is only inferred, not known directly. And if we cannot know the world directly, then one cannot EVER know of a belief about the world is TRUE or not, and JTB is unachievable. https://www.iep.utm.edu/perc-obj/#H2



      In practice today, most "reasoning" people follow a softened version of the PSR -- where "sufficient" reasons are just "supporting justifications are stronger than refutations".



      However, one can apply the Munchausen trilemma to all "supporting justifications" to challenge what THEIR support is. And the answer, in every case, because we cannot complete an infinite series, will lead to and UNJUSTIFIED supposition, or a circular argument.



      If beliefs need to be justified to be reasonably held, then all those justifications, to be held reasonably, must themselves be justified. But they are not and cannot be. The Munchausen Trilemma refutes all claims to be "reasonable" or hold "justified beliefs" based on our current standards of knowledge or reasoning.



      The response among many philosophers has been to embrace larger networks of supporting assumptions, this is the coherence reply to this dilemma. https://www.iep.utm.edu/coherent/ The reasoning is that while a simple circle might be a fallacy, a complex web of justifications is not. The name of the Munchausen Trilemma, with critiques the circularity of coherentism, is a ridicule of this claim. Baron von Munchausen cannot pull himself out of the mud, or pull his horse out of the mud, but by pulling on his hair, then lifting himself this way, he was able indirectly to lift his horse through the stirrups!



      If no beliefs are justified by our current form of rationality/reasoning, then philosophy and knowledge must both become non-rationalist. The response to this has varied between Europe and the US. In Europe, it has been an embrace of radical relativity -- IE postmodernism. In the US it has typically lead to pragmatism, where one can justify beliefs based on the pragmatic criteria of their utility/effectiveness.






      share|improve this answer

























        Your Answer








        StackExchange.ready(function()
        var channelOptions =
        tags: "".split(" "),
        id: "265"
        ;
        initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

        StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
        // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
        if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
        StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
        createEditor();
        );

        else
        createEditor();

        );

        function createEditor()
        StackExchange.prepareEditor(
        heartbeatType: 'answer',
        autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
        convertImagesToLinks: false,
        noModals: true,
        showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
        reputationToPostImages: null,
        bindNavPrevention: true,
        postfix: "",
        imageUploader:
        brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
        contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
        allowUrls: true
        ,
        noCode: true, onDemand: true,
        discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
        ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
        );



        );






        user40358 is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.









        draft saved

        draft discarded


















        StackExchange.ready(
        function ()
        StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphilosophy.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f64638%2fis-the-m%25c3%25bcnchhausen-trilemma-really-a-trilemma%23new-answer', 'question_page');

        );

        Post as a guest















        Required, but never shown

























        3 Answers
        3






        active

        oldest

        votes








        3 Answers
        3






        active

        oldest

        votes









        active

        oldest

        votes






        active

        oldest

        votes









        2














        The trilemma is about justification of a given proposition. Any justification, so the story goes, takes ultimately one of these forms if faced with skepticism.



        Therefore, the third option is about people who answer to the question "But how do you know that x really is true" dogmatically, e.g. with "Because it is", "Because I say so", etc.



        Ultimately, the answers "It is self-evident" and "Empirical research shows it" are, if taken as an end-point of justification, arbitrary since the skeptical objections "Why do you assume self-evidence here, I do not follow" and "What are the standards of this research, why should this be a particularly good standard for the truth of the proposition" are still valid.



        Sure, we accept that for statements about the world, empirical research is probably the gold standard and brings us as close to the truth as we might get, but that's not the setting in which the trilemma is supposed to work.



        It is about forms of justification, and ending the chain of justification at an arbitrary point is dogmatic, no matter how well-justified the point itself might be. If I claim that this justification was unquestionable and ultimately justifies the whole chain as true, I am dogmatic.






        share|improve this answer



























          2














          The trilemma is about justification of a given proposition. Any justification, so the story goes, takes ultimately one of these forms if faced with skepticism.



          Therefore, the third option is about people who answer to the question "But how do you know that x really is true" dogmatically, e.g. with "Because it is", "Because I say so", etc.



          Ultimately, the answers "It is self-evident" and "Empirical research shows it" are, if taken as an end-point of justification, arbitrary since the skeptical objections "Why do you assume self-evidence here, I do not follow" and "What are the standards of this research, why should this be a particularly good standard for the truth of the proposition" are still valid.



          Sure, we accept that for statements about the world, empirical research is probably the gold standard and brings us as close to the truth as we might get, but that's not the setting in which the trilemma is supposed to work.



          It is about forms of justification, and ending the chain of justification at an arbitrary point is dogmatic, no matter how well-justified the point itself might be. If I claim that this justification was unquestionable and ultimately justifies the whole chain as true, I am dogmatic.






          share|improve this answer

























            2












            2








            2







            The trilemma is about justification of a given proposition. Any justification, so the story goes, takes ultimately one of these forms if faced with skepticism.



            Therefore, the third option is about people who answer to the question "But how do you know that x really is true" dogmatically, e.g. with "Because it is", "Because I say so", etc.



            Ultimately, the answers "It is self-evident" and "Empirical research shows it" are, if taken as an end-point of justification, arbitrary since the skeptical objections "Why do you assume self-evidence here, I do not follow" and "What are the standards of this research, why should this be a particularly good standard for the truth of the proposition" are still valid.



            Sure, we accept that for statements about the world, empirical research is probably the gold standard and brings us as close to the truth as we might get, but that's not the setting in which the trilemma is supposed to work.



            It is about forms of justification, and ending the chain of justification at an arbitrary point is dogmatic, no matter how well-justified the point itself might be. If I claim that this justification was unquestionable and ultimately justifies the whole chain as true, I am dogmatic.






            share|improve this answer













            The trilemma is about justification of a given proposition. Any justification, so the story goes, takes ultimately one of these forms if faced with skepticism.



            Therefore, the third option is about people who answer to the question "But how do you know that x really is true" dogmatically, e.g. with "Because it is", "Because I say so", etc.



            Ultimately, the answers "It is self-evident" and "Empirical research shows it" are, if taken as an end-point of justification, arbitrary since the skeptical objections "Why do you assume self-evidence here, I do not follow" and "What are the standards of this research, why should this be a particularly good standard for the truth of the proposition" are still valid.



            Sure, we accept that for statements about the world, empirical research is probably the gold standard and brings us as close to the truth as we might get, but that's not the setting in which the trilemma is supposed to work.



            It is about forms of justification, and ending the chain of justification at an arbitrary point is dogmatic, no matter how well-justified the point itself might be. If I claim that this justification was unquestionable and ultimately justifies the whole chain as true, I am dogmatic.







            share|improve this answer












            share|improve this answer



            share|improve this answer










            answered 7 hours ago









            Philip KlöckingPhilip Klöcking

            7,7882 gold badges27 silver badges54 bronze badges




            7,7882 gold badges27 silver badges54 bronze badges























                2














                Circular argument



                We know it's a trilemma because the argument is founded on logic and proofs, and all proofs will end in either circular logic, infinite regression, or a foundational assumption.



                Infinite regress



                You can always break a proof into parts. Those parts get simpler and simpler. Keep breaking them up long enough, and all parts will eventually become circular logic, infinite regression, or foundational assumptions.



                Foundational assumptions



                We know it's a trilemma.




                All kidding aside, we find this pattern is generally true. Logical arguments end up in one of these buckets. Sometimes you can change which bucket it ends up in (such as calculus, which permits us to replace some infinite regression arguments like Zeno's paradox with foundational assumptions about how limits behave), but they end up in one of these buckets in the end.



                The main value of the trilemma is to provoke thought. Its to make you think about what must come of rational thought. If it does so, then it has done its job. Proving it "right" however, is more difficult. The whole point of the trilemma is that people who believe in it are not satisfied with the result of any attempt at a proof.



                To prove it, you would have to select what concept of "proof" you wish to explore and what tools you are willing to consider in the proof thereof. Those are rather personal, which means there's not a one size fits all answer, besides the satirical version I wrote above.



                I would argue that you have a clear opinion as to what proofs you find appealing. You appear to find the foundational ones appealing while the others feel like "not an argument." Consider, however, the infamous Turtles argument:




                The following anecdote is told of William James. [...] After a lecture on
                cosmology and the structure of the solar system, James was accosted by
                a little old lady.



                "Your theory that the sun is the centre of the solar system, and the
                earth is a ball which rotates around it has a very convincing ring to
                it, Mr. James, but it's wrong. I've got a better theory," said the
                little old lady.



                "And what is that, madam?" inquired James politely.



                "That we live on a crust of earth which is on the back of a giant
                turtle."



                Not wishing to demolish this absurd little theory by bringing to bear
                the masses of scientific evidence he had at his command, James decided
                to gently dissuade his opponent by making her see some of the
                inadequacies of her position.



                "If your theory is correct, madam," he asked, "what does this turtle
                stand on?"



                "You're a very clever man, Mr. James, and that's a very good
                question," replied the little old lady, "but I have an answer to it.
                And it's this: The first turtle stands on the back of a second, far
                larger, turtle, who stands directly under him."



                "But what does this second turtle stand on?" persisted James
                patiently.



                To this, the little old lady crowed triumphantly,



                "It's no use, Mr. James—it's turtles all the way down."




                Now you don't have to agree with the opinions in this story, but you must admit that there something worth calling a "proof" here, and it ends in infinite regress. As a thought experiment, how would you go about responding to this? Would you be inclined to tell the little old lady that it is not valid to use infinite regression in proofs?



                Consider how we model numbers with Peano arithmetic. We always have an axiom of induction. We may call that simply a foundational axiom, but if we look into why we think it is a valid axiom, it starts to look an aweful lot like an infinite regression argument. We just tucked it away inside a foundational axiom so that we didn't have to worry about it polluting the rest of the proofs. So, perhaps, in a way, such fundamentals of arithemtic simply prove that infinite regress is a valid method of proof in some carefully constructed circumstances!






                share|improve this answer



























                  2














                  Circular argument



                  We know it's a trilemma because the argument is founded on logic and proofs, and all proofs will end in either circular logic, infinite regression, or a foundational assumption.



                  Infinite regress



                  You can always break a proof into parts. Those parts get simpler and simpler. Keep breaking them up long enough, and all parts will eventually become circular logic, infinite regression, or foundational assumptions.



                  Foundational assumptions



                  We know it's a trilemma.




                  All kidding aside, we find this pattern is generally true. Logical arguments end up in one of these buckets. Sometimes you can change which bucket it ends up in (such as calculus, which permits us to replace some infinite regression arguments like Zeno's paradox with foundational assumptions about how limits behave), but they end up in one of these buckets in the end.



                  The main value of the trilemma is to provoke thought. Its to make you think about what must come of rational thought. If it does so, then it has done its job. Proving it "right" however, is more difficult. The whole point of the trilemma is that people who believe in it are not satisfied with the result of any attempt at a proof.



                  To prove it, you would have to select what concept of "proof" you wish to explore and what tools you are willing to consider in the proof thereof. Those are rather personal, which means there's not a one size fits all answer, besides the satirical version I wrote above.



                  I would argue that you have a clear opinion as to what proofs you find appealing. You appear to find the foundational ones appealing while the others feel like "not an argument." Consider, however, the infamous Turtles argument:




                  The following anecdote is told of William James. [...] After a lecture on
                  cosmology and the structure of the solar system, James was accosted by
                  a little old lady.



                  "Your theory that the sun is the centre of the solar system, and the
                  earth is a ball which rotates around it has a very convincing ring to
                  it, Mr. James, but it's wrong. I've got a better theory," said the
                  little old lady.



                  "And what is that, madam?" inquired James politely.



                  "That we live on a crust of earth which is on the back of a giant
                  turtle."



                  Not wishing to demolish this absurd little theory by bringing to bear
                  the masses of scientific evidence he had at his command, James decided
                  to gently dissuade his opponent by making her see some of the
                  inadequacies of her position.



                  "If your theory is correct, madam," he asked, "what does this turtle
                  stand on?"



                  "You're a very clever man, Mr. James, and that's a very good
                  question," replied the little old lady, "but I have an answer to it.
                  And it's this: The first turtle stands on the back of a second, far
                  larger, turtle, who stands directly under him."



                  "But what does this second turtle stand on?" persisted James
                  patiently.



                  To this, the little old lady crowed triumphantly,



                  "It's no use, Mr. James—it's turtles all the way down."




                  Now you don't have to agree with the opinions in this story, but you must admit that there something worth calling a "proof" here, and it ends in infinite regress. As a thought experiment, how would you go about responding to this? Would you be inclined to tell the little old lady that it is not valid to use infinite regression in proofs?



                  Consider how we model numbers with Peano arithmetic. We always have an axiom of induction. We may call that simply a foundational axiom, but if we look into why we think it is a valid axiom, it starts to look an aweful lot like an infinite regression argument. We just tucked it away inside a foundational axiom so that we didn't have to worry about it polluting the rest of the proofs. So, perhaps, in a way, such fundamentals of arithemtic simply prove that infinite regress is a valid method of proof in some carefully constructed circumstances!






                  share|improve this answer

























                    2












                    2








                    2







                    Circular argument



                    We know it's a trilemma because the argument is founded on logic and proofs, and all proofs will end in either circular logic, infinite regression, or a foundational assumption.



                    Infinite regress



                    You can always break a proof into parts. Those parts get simpler and simpler. Keep breaking them up long enough, and all parts will eventually become circular logic, infinite regression, or foundational assumptions.



                    Foundational assumptions



                    We know it's a trilemma.




                    All kidding aside, we find this pattern is generally true. Logical arguments end up in one of these buckets. Sometimes you can change which bucket it ends up in (such as calculus, which permits us to replace some infinite regression arguments like Zeno's paradox with foundational assumptions about how limits behave), but they end up in one of these buckets in the end.



                    The main value of the trilemma is to provoke thought. Its to make you think about what must come of rational thought. If it does so, then it has done its job. Proving it "right" however, is more difficult. The whole point of the trilemma is that people who believe in it are not satisfied with the result of any attempt at a proof.



                    To prove it, you would have to select what concept of "proof" you wish to explore and what tools you are willing to consider in the proof thereof. Those are rather personal, which means there's not a one size fits all answer, besides the satirical version I wrote above.



                    I would argue that you have a clear opinion as to what proofs you find appealing. You appear to find the foundational ones appealing while the others feel like "not an argument." Consider, however, the infamous Turtles argument:




                    The following anecdote is told of William James. [...] After a lecture on
                    cosmology and the structure of the solar system, James was accosted by
                    a little old lady.



                    "Your theory that the sun is the centre of the solar system, and the
                    earth is a ball which rotates around it has a very convincing ring to
                    it, Mr. James, but it's wrong. I've got a better theory," said the
                    little old lady.



                    "And what is that, madam?" inquired James politely.



                    "That we live on a crust of earth which is on the back of a giant
                    turtle."



                    Not wishing to demolish this absurd little theory by bringing to bear
                    the masses of scientific evidence he had at his command, James decided
                    to gently dissuade his opponent by making her see some of the
                    inadequacies of her position.



                    "If your theory is correct, madam," he asked, "what does this turtle
                    stand on?"



                    "You're a very clever man, Mr. James, and that's a very good
                    question," replied the little old lady, "but I have an answer to it.
                    And it's this: The first turtle stands on the back of a second, far
                    larger, turtle, who stands directly under him."



                    "But what does this second turtle stand on?" persisted James
                    patiently.



                    To this, the little old lady crowed triumphantly,



                    "It's no use, Mr. James—it's turtles all the way down."




                    Now you don't have to agree with the opinions in this story, but you must admit that there something worth calling a "proof" here, and it ends in infinite regress. As a thought experiment, how would you go about responding to this? Would you be inclined to tell the little old lady that it is not valid to use infinite regression in proofs?



                    Consider how we model numbers with Peano arithmetic. We always have an axiom of induction. We may call that simply a foundational axiom, but if we look into why we think it is a valid axiom, it starts to look an aweful lot like an infinite regression argument. We just tucked it away inside a foundational axiom so that we didn't have to worry about it polluting the rest of the proofs. So, perhaps, in a way, such fundamentals of arithemtic simply prove that infinite regress is a valid method of proof in some carefully constructed circumstances!






                    share|improve this answer













                    Circular argument



                    We know it's a trilemma because the argument is founded on logic and proofs, and all proofs will end in either circular logic, infinite regression, or a foundational assumption.



                    Infinite regress



                    You can always break a proof into parts. Those parts get simpler and simpler. Keep breaking them up long enough, and all parts will eventually become circular logic, infinite regression, or foundational assumptions.



                    Foundational assumptions



                    We know it's a trilemma.




                    All kidding aside, we find this pattern is generally true. Logical arguments end up in one of these buckets. Sometimes you can change which bucket it ends up in (such as calculus, which permits us to replace some infinite regression arguments like Zeno's paradox with foundational assumptions about how limits behave), but they end up in one of these buckets in the end.



                    The main value of the trilemma is to provoke thought. Its to make you think about what must come of rational thought. If it does so, then it has done its job. Proving it "right" however, is more difficult. The whole point of the trilemma is that people who believe in it are not satisfied with the result of any attempt at a proof.



                    To prove it, you would have to select what concept of "proof" you wish to explore and what tools you are willing to consider in the proof thereof. Those are rather personal, which means there's not a one size fits all answer, besides the satirical version I wrote above.



                    I would argue that you have a clear opinion as to what proofs you find appealing. You appear to find the foundational ones appealing while the others feel like "not an argument." Consider, however, the infamous Turtles argument:




                    The following anecdote is told of William James. [...] After a lecture on
                    cosmology and the structure of the solar system, James was accosted by
                    a little old lady.



                    "Your theory that the sun is the centre of the solar system, and the
                    earth is a ball which rotates around it has a very convincing ring to
                    it, Mr. James, but it's wrong. I've got a better theory," said the
                    little old lady.



                    "And what is that, madam?" inquired James politely.



                    "That we live on a crust of earth which is on the back of a giant
                    turtle."



                    Not wishing to demolish this absurd little theory by bringing to bear
                    the masses of scientific evidence he had at his command, James decided
                    to gently dissuade his opponent by making her see some of the
                    inadequacies of her position.



                    "If your theory is correct, madam," he asked, "what does this turtle
                    stand on?"



                    "You're a very clever man, Mr. James, and that's a very good
                    question," replied the little old lady, "but I have an answer to it.
                    And it's this: The first turtle stands on the back of a second, far
                    larger, turtle, who stands directly under him."



                    "But what does this second turtle stand on?" persisted James
                    patiently.



                    To this, the little old lady crowed triumphantly,



                    "It's no use, Mr. James—it's turtles all the way down."




                    Now you don't have to agree with the opinions in this story, but you must admit that there something worth calling a "proof" here, and it ends in infinite regress. As a thought experiment, how would you go about responding to this? Would you be inclined to tell the little old lady that it is not valid to use infinite regression in proofs?



                    Consider how we model numbers with Peano arithmetic. We always have an axiom of induction. We may call that simply a foundational axiom, but if we look into why we think it is a valid axiom, it starts to look an aweful lot like an infinite regression argument. We just tucked it away inside a foundational axiom so that we didn't have to worry about it polluting the rest of the proofs. So, perhaps, in a way, such fundamentals of arithemtic simply prove that infinite regress is a valid method of proof in some carefully constructed circumstances!







                    share|improve this answer












                    share|improve this answer



                    share|improve this answer










                    answered 6 hours ago









                    Cort AmmonCort Ammon

                    14.9k12 silver badges43 bronze badges




                    14.9k12 silver badges43 bronze badges





















                        1














                        You have misunderstood the point of the Munchausen Trilemma. It plays a key role in the process of philopshy showing that none of our beliefs are justified knowledge, per the standards of "reasoning".



                        Most people hold that they have knowledge and beliefs based on justified reasons, and that beliefs SHOULD be justified, and knowledge isn't knowledge unless it is justified somehow. The term for this is the Principle of Sufficient Reason: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sufficient-reason/



                        In its first usage, by Spinoza and Leibniz, the PSR basically called for a proof, before one could satisfy it.



                        Another key term in the history of knowledge is Justified True Belief -- the criteria that knowledge is only knowledge if one has both justifications, AND it is true. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-analysis/



                        However, most empiricists since Locke have been indirect realists -- holding that the world is only inferred, not known directly. And if we cannot know the world directly, then one cannot EVER know of a belief about the world is TRUE or not, and JTB is unachievable. https://www.iep.utm.edu/perc-obj/#H2



                        In practice today, most "reasoning" people follow a softened version of the PSR -- where "sufficient" reasons are just "supporting justifications are stronger than refutations".



                        However, one can apply the Munchausen trilemma to all "supporting justifications" to challenge what THEIR support is. And the answer, in every case, because we cannot complete an infinite series, will lead to and UNJUSTIFIED supposition, or a circular argument.



                        If beliefs need to be justified to be reasonably held, then all those justifications, to be held reasonably, must themselves be justified. But they are not and cannot be. The Munchausen Trilemma refutes all claims to be "reasonable" or hold "justified beliefs" based on our current standards of knowledge or reasoning.



                        The response among many philosophers has been to embrace larger networks of supporting assumptions, this is the coherence reply to this dilemma. https://www.iep.utm.edu/coherent/ The reasoning is that while a simple circle might be a fallacy, a complex web of justifications is not. The name of the Munchausen Trilemma, with critiques the circularity of coherentism, is a ridicule of this claim. Baron von Munchausen cannot pull himself out of the mud, or pull his horse out of the mud, but by pulling on his hair, then lifting himself this way, he was able indirectly to lift his horse through the stirrups!



                        If no beliefs are justified by our current form of rationality/reasoning, then philosophy and knowledge must both become non-rationalist. The response to this has varied between Europe and the US. In Europe, it has been an embrace of radical relativity -- IE postmodernism. In the US it has typically lead to pragmatism, where one can justify beliefs based on the pragmatic criteria of their utility/effectiveness.






                        share|improve this answer



























                          1














                          You have misunderstood the point of the Munchausen Trilemma. It plays a key role in the process of philopshy showing that none of our beliefs are justified knowledge, per the standards of "reasoning".



                          Most people hold that they have knowledge and beliefs based on justified reasons, and that beliefs SHOULD be justified, and knowledge isn't knowledge unless it is justified somehow. The term for this is the Principle of Sufficient Reason: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sufficient-reason/



                          In its first usage, by Spinoza and Leibniz, the PSR basically called for a proof, before one could satisfy it.



                          Another key term in the history of knowledge is Justified True Belief -- the criteria that knowledge is only knowledge if one has both justifications, AND it is true. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-analysis/



                          However, most empiricists since Locke have been indirect realists -- holding that the world is only inferred, not known directly. And if we cannot know the world directly, then one cannot EVER know of a belief about the world is TRUE or not, and JTB is unachievable. https://www.iep.utm.edu/perc-obj/#H2



                          In practice today, most "reasoning" people follow a softened version of the PSR -- where "sufficient" reasons are just "supporting justifications are stronger than refutations".



                          However, one can apply the Munchausen trilemma to all "supporting justifications" to challenge what THEIR support is. And the answer, in every case, because we cannot complete an infinite series, will lead to and UNJUSTIFIED supposition, or a circular argument.



                          If beliefs need to be justified to be reasonably held, then all those justifications, to be held reasonably, must themselves be justified. But they are not and cannot be. The Munchausen Trilemma refutes all claims to be "reasonable" or hold "justified beliefs" based on our current standards of knowledge or reasoning.



                          The response among many philosophers has been to embrace larger networks of supporting assumptions, this is the coherence reply to this dilemma. https://www.iep.utm.edu/coherent/ The reasoning is that while a simple circle might be a fallacy, a complex web of justifications is not. The name of the Munchausen Trilemma, with critiques the circularity of coherentism, is a ridicule of this claim. Baron von Munchausen cannot pull himself out of the mud, or pull his horse out of the mud, but by pulling on his hair, then lifting himself this way, he was able indirectly to lift his horse through the stirrups!



                          If no beliefs are justified by our current form of rationality/reasoning, then philosophy and knowledge must both become non-rationalist. The response to this has varied between Europe and the US. In Europe, it has been an embrace of radical relativity -- IE postmodernism. In the US it has typically lead to pragmatism, where one can justify beliefs based on the pragmatic criteria of their utility/effectiveness.






                          share|improve this answer

























                            1












                            1








                            1







                            You have misunderstood the point of the Munchausen Trilemma. It plays a key role in the process of philopshy showing that none of our beliefs are justified knowledge, per the standards of "reasoning".



                            Most people hold that they have knowledge and beliefs based on justified reasons, and that beliefs SHOULD be justified, and knowledge isn't knowledge unless it is justified somehow. The term for this is the Principle of Sufficient Reason: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sufficient-reason/



                            In its first usage, by Spinoza and Leibniz, the PSR basically called for a proof, before one could satisfy it.



                            Another key term in the history of knowledge is Justified True Belief -- the criteria that knowledge is only knowledge if one has both justifications, AND it is true. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-analysis/



                            However, most empiricists since Locke have been indirect realists -- holding that the world is only inferred, not known directly. And if we cannot know the world directly, then one cannot EVER know of a belief about the world is TRUE or not, and JTB is unachievable. https://www.iep.utm.edu/perc-obj/#H2



                            In practice today, most "reasoning" people follow a softened version of the PSR -- where "sufficient" reasons are just "supporting justifications are stronger than refutations".



                            However, one can apply the Munchausen trilemma to all "supporting justifications" to challenge what THEIR support is. And the answer, in every case, because we cannot complete an infinite series, will lead to and UNJUSTIFIED supposition, or a circular argument.



                            If beliefs need to be justified to be reasonably held, then all those justifications, to be held reasonably, must themselves be justified. But they are not and cannot be. The Munchausen Trilemma refutes all claims to be "reasonable" or hold "justified beliefs" based on our current standards of knowledge or reasoning.



                            The response among many philosophers has been to embrace larger networks of supporting assumptions, this is the coherence reply to this dilemma. https://www.iep.utm.edu/coherent/ The reasoning is that while a simple circle might be a fallacy, a complex web of justifications is not. The name of the Munchausen Trilemma, with critiques the circularity of coherentism, is a ridicule of this claim. Baron von Munchausen cannot pull himself out of the mud, or pull his horse out of the mud, but by pulling on his hair, then lifting himself this way, he was able indirectly to lift his horse through the stirrups!



                            If no beliefs are justified by our current form of rationality/reasoning, then philosophy and knowledge must both become non-rationalist. The response to this has varied between Europe and the US. In Europe, it has been an embrace of radical relativity -- IE postmodernism. In the US it has typically lead to pragmatism, where one can justify beliefs based on the pragmatic criteria of their utility/effectiveness.






                            share|improve this answer













                            You have misunderstood the point of the Munchausen Trilemma. It plays a key role in the process of philopshy showing that none of our beliefs are justified knowledge, per the standards of "reasoning".



                            Most people hold that they have knowledge and beliefs based on justified reasons, and that beliefs SHOULD be justified, and knowledge isn't knowledge unless it is justified somehow. The term for this is the Principle of Sufficient Reason: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sufficient-reason/



                            In its first usage, by Spinoza and Leibniz, the PSR basically called for a proof, before one could satisfy it.



                            Another key term in the history of knowledge is Justified True Belief -- the criteria that knowledge is only knowledge if one has both justifications, AND it is true. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-analysis/



                            However, most empiricists since Locke have been indirect realists -- holding that the world is only inferred, not known directly. And if we cannot know the world directly, then one cannot EVER know of a belief about the world is TRUE or not, and JTB is unachievable. https://www.iep.utm.edu/perc-obj/#H2



                            In practice today, most "reasoning" people follow a softened version of the PSR -- where "sufficient" reasons are just "supporting justifications are stronger than refutations".



                            However, one can apply the Munchausen trilemma to all "supporting justifications" to challenge what THEIR support is. And the answer, in every case, because we cannot complete an infinite series, will lead to and UNJUSTIFIED supposition, or a circular argument.



                            If beliefs need to be justified to be reasonably held, then all those justifications, to be held reasonably, must themselves be justified. But they are not and cannot be. The Munchausen Trilemma refutes all claims to be "reasonable" or hold "justified beliefs" based on our current standards of knowledge or reasoning.



                            The response among many philosophers has been to embrace larger networks of supporting assumptions, this is the coherence reply to this dilemma. https://www.iep.utm.edu/coherent/ The reasoning is that while a simple circle might be a fallacy, a complex web of justifications is not. The name of the Munchausen Trilemma, with critiques the circularity of coherentism, is a ridicule of this claim. Baron von Munchausen cannot pull himself out of the mud, or pull his horse out of the mud, but by pulling on his hair, then lifting himself this way, he was able indirectly to lift his horse through the stirrups!



                            If no beliefs are justified by our current form of rationality/reasoning, then philosophy and knowledge must both become non-rationalist. The response to this has varied between Europe and the US. In Europe, it has been an embrace of radical relativity -- IE postmodernism. In the US it has typically lead to pragmatism, where one can justify beliefs based on the pragmatic criteria of their utility/effectiveness.







                            share|improve this answer












                            share|improve this answer



                            share|improve this answer










                            answered 5 hours ago









                            DcleveDcleve

                            1,4131 gold badge3 silver badges20 bronze badges




                            1,4131 gold badge3 silver badges20 bronze badges




















                                user40358 is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.









                                draft saved

                                draft discarded


















                                user40358 is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.












                                user40358 is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.











                                user40358 is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.














                                Thanks for contributing an answer to Philosophy Stack Exchange!


                                • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                                But avoid


                                • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                                • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.

                                To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                                draft saved


                                draft discarded














                                StackExchange.ready(
                                function ()
                                StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphilosophy.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f64638%2fis-the-m%25c3%25bcnchhausen-trilemma-really-a-trilemma%23new-answer', 'question_page');

                                );

                                Post as a guest















                                Required, but never shown





















































                                Required, but never shown














                                Required, but never shown












                                Required, but never shown







                                Required, but never shown

































                                Required, but never shown














                                Required, but never shown












                                Required, but never shown







                                Required, but never shown







                                Popular posts from this blog

                                Invision Community Contents History See also References External links Navigation menuProprietaryinvisioncommunity.comIPS Community ForumsIPS Community Forumsthis blog entry"License Changes, IP.Board 3.4, and the Future""Interview -- Matt Mecham of Ibforums""CEO Invision Power Board, Matt Mecham Is a Liar, Thief!"IPB License Explanation 1.3, 1.3.1, 2.0, and 2.1ArchivedSecurity Fixes, Updates And Enhancements For IPB 1.3.1Archived"New Demo Accounts - Invision Power Services"the original"New Default Skin"the original"Invision Power Board 3.0.0 and Applications Released"the original"Archived copy"the original"Perpetual licenses being done away with""Release Notes - Invision Power Services""Introducing: IPS Community Suite 4!"Invision Community Release Notes

                                Canceling a color specificationRandomly assigning color to Graphics3D objects?Default color for Filling in Mathematica 9Coloring specific elements of sets with a prime modified order in an array plotHow to pick a color differing significantly from the colors already in a given color list?Detection of the text colorColor numbers based on their valueCan color schemes for use with ColorData include opacity specification?My dynamic color schemes

                                Ласкавець круглолистий Зміст Опис | Поширення | Галерея | Примітки | Посилання | Навігаційне меню58171138361-22960890446Bupleurum rotundifoliumEuro+Med PlantbasePlants of the World Online — Kew ScienceGermplasm Resources Information Network (GRIN)Ласкавецькн. VI : Літери Ком — Левиправивши або дописавши її